ocsenave@0
|
1 #+TITLE: Statistical Mechanics
|
ocsenave@0
|
2 #+AUTHOR: E.T. Jaynes; edited by Dylan Holmes
|
ocsenave@0
|
3 #+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu
|
ocsenave@0
|
4 #+KEYWORDS: statistical mechanics, thermostatics, thermodynamics, temperature, paradoxes, Jaynes
|
ocsenave@0
|
5 #+SETUPFILE: ../../aurellem/org/setup.org
|
ocsenave@0
|
6 #+INCLUDE: ../../aurellem/org/level-0.org
|
ocsenave@0
|
7 #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"http://www.aurellem.org/MathJax/MathJax.js"
|
ocsenave@0
|
8
|
ocsenave@0
|
9 # "extensions/eqn-number.js"
|
ocsenave@0
|
10
|
ocsenave@0
|
11 #+begin_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
12 *Note:* The following is a typeset version of
|
ocsenave@0
|
13 [[../sources/stat.mech.1.pdf][this unpublished book draft]], written by [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Edwin_Thompson_Jaynes][E.T. Jaynes]]. I have only made
|
ocsenave@0
|
14 minor changes, e.g. to correct typographical errors, add references, or format equations. The
|
ocsenave@0
|
15 content itself is intact. --- Dylan
|
ocsenave@0
|
16 #+end_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
17
|
ocsenave@0
|
18 * Development of Thermodynamics
|
ocsenave@0
|
19 Our first intuitive, or \ldquo{}subjective\rdquo{} notions of temperature
|
ocsenave@0
|
20 arise from the sensations of warmth and cold associated with our
|
ocsenave@0
|
21 sense of touch . Yet science has been able to convert this qualitative
|
ocsenave@0
|
22 sensation into an accurately defined quantitative notion,
|
ocsenave@0
|
23 which can be applied far beyond the range of our direct experience.
|
ocsenave@0
|
24 Today an experimentalist will report confidently that his
|
ocsenave@0
|
25 spin system was at a temperature of 2.51 degrees Kelvin; and a
|
ocsenave@0
|
26 theoretician will report with almost as much confidence that the
|
ocsenave@0
|
27 temperature at the center of the sun is about \(2 \times 10^7\) degrees
|
ocsenave@0
|
28 Kelvin.
|
ocsenave@0
|
29
|
ocsenave@0
|
30 The /fact/ that this has proved possible, and the main technical
|
ocsenave@0
|
31 ideas involved, are assumed already known to the reader;
|
ocsenave@0
|
32 and we are not concerned here with repeating standard material
|
ocsenave@0
|
33 already available in a dozen other textbooks . However
|
ocsenave@0
|
34 thermodynamics, in spite of its great successes, firmly established
|
ocsenave@0
|
35 for over a century, has also produced a great deal of confusion
|
ocsenave@0
|
36 and a long list of \ldquo{}paradoxes\rdquo{} centering mostly
|
ocsenave@0
|
37 around the second law and the nature of irreversibility.
|
ocsenave@0
|
38 For this reason and others noted below, we want to dwell here at
|
ocsenave@0
|
39 some length on the /logic/ underlying the development of
|
ocsenave@0
|
40 thermodynamics . Our aim is to emphasize certain points which,
|
ocsenave@0
|
41 in the writer's opinion, are essential for clearing up the
|
ocsenave@0
|
42 confusion and resolving the paradoxes; but which are not
|
ocsenave@0
|
43 sufficiently ernphasized---and indeed in many cases are
|
ocsenave@0
|
44 totally ignored---in other textbooks.
|
ocsenave@0
|
45
|
ocsenave@0
|
46 This attention to logic
|
ocsenave@0
|
47 would not be particularly needed if we regarded classical
|
ocsenave@0
|
48 thermodynamics (or, as it is becoming called increasingly,
|
ocsenave@0
|
49 /thermostatics/) as a closed subject, in which the fundamentals
|
ocsenave@0
|
50 are already completely established, and there is
|
ocsenave@0
|
51 nothing more to be learned about them. A person who believes
|
ocsenave@0
|
52 this will probably prefer a pure axiomatic approach, in which
|
ocsenave@0
|
53 the basic laws are simply stated as arbitrary axioms, without
|
ocsenave@0
|
54 any attempt to present the evidence for them; and one proceeds
|
ocsenave@0
|
55 directly to working out their consequences.
|
ocsenave@0
|
56 However, we take the attitude here that thermostatics, for
|
ocsenave@0
|
57 all its venerable age, is very far from being a closed subject,
|
ocsenave@0
|
58 we still have a great deal to learn about such matters as the
|
ocsenave@0
|
59 most general definitions of equilibrium and reversibility, the
|
ocsenave@0
|
60 exact range of validity of various statements of the second and
|
ocsenave@0
|
61 third laws, the necessary and sufficient conditions for
|
ocsenave@0
|
62 applicability of thermodynamics to special cases such as
|
ocsenave@0
|
63 spin systems, and how thermodynamics can be applied to such
|
ocsenave@0
|
64 systems as putty or polyethylene, which deform under force,
|
ocsenave@0
|
65 but retain a \ldquo{}memory\rdquo{} of their past deformations.
|
ocsenave@0
|
66 Is it possible to apply thermodynamics to a system such as a vibrating quartz crystal? We can by
|
ocsenave@0
|
67 no means rule out the possibility that still more laws of
|
ocsenave@0
|
68 thermodynamics exist, as yet undiscovered, which would be
|
ocsenave@0
|
69 useful in such applications.
|
ocsenave@0
|
70
|
ocsenave@0
|
71
|
ocsenave@0
|
72 It is only by careful examination of the logic by which
|
ocsenave@0
|
73 present thermodynamics was created, asking exactly how much of
|
ocsenave@0
|
74 it is mathematical theorems, how much is deducible from the laws
|
ocsenave@0
|
75 of mechanics and electrodynamics, and how much rests only on
|
ocsenave@0
|
76 empirical evidence, how compelling is present evidence for the
|
ocsenave@0
|
77 accuracy and range of validity of its laws; in other words,
|
ocsenave@0
|
78 exactly where are the boundaries of present knowledge, that we
|
ocsenave@0
|
79 can hope to uncover new things. Clearly, much research is still
|
ocsenave@0
|
80 needed in this field, and we shall be able to accomplish only a
|
ocsenave@0
|
81 small part of this program in the present review.
|
ocsenave@0
|
82
|
ocsenave@0
|
83
|
ocsenave@0
|
84 It will develop that there is an astonishingly close analogy
|
ocsenave@0
|
85 with the logic underlying statistical theory in general, where
|
ocsenave@0
|
86 again a qualitative feeling that we all have (for the degrees of
|
ocsenave@0
|
87 plausibility of various unproved and undisproved assertions) must
|
ocsenave@0
|
88 be convertefi into a precisely defined quantitative concept
|
ocsenave@0
|
89 (probability). Our later development of probability theory in
|
ocsenave@0
|
90 Chapter 6,7 will be, to a considerable degree, a paraphrase
|
ocsenave@0
|
91 of our present review of the logic underlying classical
|
ocsenave@0
|
92 thermodynamics.
|
ocsenave@0
|
93
|
ocsenave@0
|
94 ** The Primitive Thermometer.
|
ocsenave@0
|
95
|
ocsenave@0
|
96 The earliest stages of our
|
ocsenave@0
|
97 story are necessarily speculative, since they took place long
|
ocsenave@0
|
98 before the beginnings of recorded history. But we can hardly
|
ocsenave@0
|
99 doubt that primitive man learned quickly that objects exposed
|
ocsenave@0
|
100 to the sun‘s rays or placed near a fire felt different from
|
ocsenave@0
|
101 those in the shade away from fires; and the same difference was
|
ocsenave@0
|
102 noted between animal bodies and inanimate objects.
|
ocsenave@0
|
103
|
ocsenave@0
|
104
|
ocsenave@0
|
105 As soon as it was noted that changes in this feeling of
|
ocsenave@0
|
106 warmth were correlated with other observable changes in the
|
ocsenave@0
|
107 behavior of objects, such as the boiling and freezing of water,
|
ocsenave@0
|
108 cooking of meat, melting of fat and wax, etc., the notion of
|
ocsenave@0
|
109 warmth took its first step away from the purely subjective
|
ocsenave@0
|
110 toward an objective, physical notion capable of being studied
|
ocsenave@0
|
111 scientifically.
|
ocsenave@0
|
112
|
ocsenave@0
|
113 One of the most striking manifestations of warmth (but far
|
ocsenave@0
|
114 from the earliest discovered) is the almost universal expansion
|
ocsenave@0
|
115 of gases, liquids, and solids when heated . This property has
|
ocsenave@0
|
116 proved to be a convenient one with which to reduce the notion
|
ocsenave@0
|
117 of warmth to something entirely objective. The invention of the
|
ocsenave@0
|
118 /thermometer/, in which expansion of a mercury column, or a gas,
|
ocsenave@0
|
119 or the bending of a bimetallic strip, etc. is read off on a
|
ocsenave@0
|
120 suitable scale, thereby giving us a /number/ with which to work,
|
ocsenave@0
|
121 was a necessary prelude to even the crudest study of the physical
|
ocsenave@0
|
122 nature of heat. To the best of our knowledge, although the
|
ocsenave@0
|
123 necessary technology to do this had been available for at least
|
ocsenave@0
|
124 3,000 years, the first person to carry it out in practice was
|
ocsenave@0
|
125 Galileo, in 1592.
|
ocsenave@0
|
126
|
ocsenave@0
|
127 Later on we will give more precise definitions of the term
|
ocsenave@0
|
128 \ldquo{}thermometer.\rdquo{} But at the present stage we
|
ocsenave@0
|
129 are not in a position to do so (as Galileo was not), because
|
ocsenave@0
|
130 the very concepts needed have not yet been developed;
|
ocsenave@0
|
131 more precise definitions can be
|
ocsenave@0
|
132 given only after our study has revealed the need for them. In
|
ocsenave@0
|
133 deed, our final definition can be given only after the full
|
ocsenave@0
|
134 mathematical formalism of statistical mechanics is at hand.
|
ocsenave@0
|
135
|
ocsenave@0
|
136 Once a thermometer has been constructed, and the scale
|
ocsenave@0
|
137 marked off in a quite arbitrary way (although we will suppose
|
ocsenave@0
|
138 that the scale is at least monotonic: i.e., greater warmth always
|
ocsenave@0
|
139 corresponds to a greater number), we are ready to begin scien
|
ocsenave@0
|
140 tific experiments in thermodynamics. The number read eff from
|
ocsenave@0
|
141 any such instrument is called the /empirical temperature/, and we
|
ocsenave@0
|
142 denote it by \(t\). Since the exact calibration of the thermometer
|
ocsenave@0
|
143 is not specified), any monotonic increasing function
|
ocsenave@0
|
144 \(t‘ = f(t)\) provides an equally good temperature scale for the
|
ocsenave@0
|
145 present.
|
ocsenave@0
|
146
|
ocsenave@0
|
147
|
ocsenave@0
|
148 ** Thermodynamic Systems.
|
ocsenave@0
|
149
|
ocsenave@0
|
150 The \ldquo{}thermodynamic systems\rdquo{} which
|
ocsenave@0
|
151 are the objects of our study may be, physically, almost any
|
ocsenave@0
|
152 collections of objects. The traditional simplest system with
|
ocsenave@0
|
153 which to begin a study of thermodynamics is a volume of gas.
|
ocsenave@0
|
154 We shall, however, be concerned from the start also with such
|
ocsenave@0
|
155 things as a stretched wire or membrane, an electric cell, a
|
ocsenave@0
|
156 polarized dielectric, a paramagnetic body in a magnetic field, etc.
|
ocsenave@0
|
157
|
ocsenave@0
|
158 The /thermodynamic state/ of such a system is determined by
|
ocsenave@0
|
159 specifying (i.e., measuring) certain macrcoscopic physical
|
ocsenave@0
|
160 properties. Now, any real physical system has many millions of such
|
ocsenave@0
|
161 preperties; in order to have a usable theory we cannot require
|
ocsenave@0
|
162 that /all/ of them be specified. We see, therefore, that there
|
ocsenave@0
|
163 must be a clear distinction between the notions of
|
ocsenave@0
|
164 \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} and \ldquo{}physical
|
ocsenave@0
|
165 system.\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
166 A given /physical/ system may correspond to many different
|
ocsenave@0
|
167 /thermodynamic systems/, depending
|
ocsenave@0
|
168 on which variables we choose to measure or control; and which
|
ocsenave@0
|
169 we decide to leave unmeasured and/or uncontrolled.
|
ocsenave@0
|
170
|
ocsenave@0
|
171
|
ocsenave@0
|
172 For example, our physical system might consist of a crystal
|
ocsenave@0
|
173 of sodium chloride. For one set of experiments we work with
|
ocsenave@0
|
174 temperature, volume, and pressure; and ignore its electrical
|
ocsenave@0
|
175 properties. For another set of experiments we work with
|
ocsenave@0
|
176 temperature, electric field, and electric polarization; and
|
ocsenave@0
|
177 ignore the varying stress and strain. The /physical/ system,
|
ocsenave@0
|
178 therefore, corresponds to two entirely different /thermodynamic/
|
ocsenave@0
|
179 systems. Exactly how much freedom, then, do we have in choosing
|
ocsenave@0
|
180 the variables which shall define the thermodynamic state of our
|
ocsenave@0
|
181 system? How many must we choose? What [criteria] determine when
|
ocsenave@0
|
182 we have made an adequate choice? These questions cannot be
|
ocsenave@0
|
183 answered until we say a little more about what we are trying to
|
ocsenave@0
|
184 accomplish by a thermodynamic theory. A mere collection of
|
ocsenave@0
|
185 recorded data about our system, as in the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CRC_Handbook_of_Chemistry_and_Physics][/Handbook of Physics and
|
ocsenave@0
|
186 Chemistry/]], is a very useful thing, but it hardly constitutes
|
ocsenave@0
|
187 a theory. In order to construct anything deserving of such a
|
ocsenave@0
|
188 name, the primary requirement is that we can recognize some kind
|
ocsenave@0
|
189 of reproducible connection between the different properties con
|
ocsenave@0
|
190 sidered, so that information about some of them will enable us
|
ocsenave@0
|
191 to predict others. And of course, in order that our theory can
|
ocsenave@0
|
192 be called thermodynamics (and not some other area of physics),
|
ocsenave@0
|
193 it is necessary that the temperature be one of the quantities
|
ocsenave@0
|
194 involved in a nontrivial way.
|
ocsenave@0
|
195
|
ocsenave@0
|
196 The gist of these remarks is that the notion of
|
ocsenave@0
|
197 \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} is in part
|
ocsenave@0
|
198 an anthropomorphic one; it is for us to
|
ocsenave@0
|
199 say which set of variables shall be used. If two different
|
ocsenave@0
|
200 choices both lead to useful reproducible connections, it is quite
|
ocsenave@0
|
201 meaningless to say that one choice is any more \ldquo{}correct\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
202 than the other. Recognition of this fact will prove crucial later in
|
ocsenave@0
|
203 avoiding certain ancient paradoxes.
|
ocsenave@0
|
204
|
ocsenave@0
|
205 At this stage we can determine only empirically which other
|
ocsenave@0
|
206 physical properties need to be introduced before reproducible
|
ocsenave@0
|
207 connections appear. Once any such connection is established, we
|
ocsenave@0
|
208 can analyze it with the hope of being able to (1) reduce it to a
|
ocsenave@0
|
209 /logical/ connection rather than an empirical one; and (2) extend
|
ocsenave@0
|
210 it to an hypothesis applying beyond the original data, which
|
ocsenave@0
|
211 enables us to predict further connections capable of being
|
ocsenave@0
|
212 tested by experiment. Examples of this will be given presently.
|
ocsenave@0
|
213
|
ocsenave@0
|
214
|
ocsenave@0
|
215 There will remain, however, a few reproducible relations
|
ocsenave@0
|
216 which to the best of present knowledge, are not reducible to
|
ocsenave@0
|
217 logical relations within the context of classical thermodynamics
|
ocsenave@0
|
218 (and. whose demonstration in the wider context of mechanics,
|
ocsenave@0
|
219 electrodynamics, and quantum theory remains one of probability
|
ocsenave@0
|
220 rather than logical proof); from the standpoint of thermodynamics
|
ocsenave@0
|
221 these remain simply statements of empirical fact which must be
|
ocsenave@0
|
222 accepted as such without any deeper basis, but without which the
|
ocsenave@0
|
223 development of thermodynamics cannot proceed. Because of this
|
ocsenave@0
|
224 special status, these relations have become known as the
|
ocsenave@0
|
225 \ldquo{}laws\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
226 of thermodynamics . The most fundamental one is a qualitative
|
ocsenave@0
|
227 rather than quantitative relation, the \ldquo{}zero'th law.\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
228
|
ocsenave@0
|
229 ** Equilibrium; the \ldquo{}Zero‘th Law.\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
230
|
ocsenave@0
|
231 It is a common experience
|
ocsenave@0
|
232 that when objects are placed in contact with each other but
|
ocsenave@0
|
233 isolated from their surroundings, they may undergo observable
|
ocsenave@0
|
234 changes for a time as a result; one body may become warmer,
|
ocsenave@0
|
235 another cooler, the pressure of a gas or volume of a liquid may
|
ocsenave@0
|
236 change; stress or magnetization in a solid may change, etc. But
|
ocsenave@0
|
237 after a sufficient time, the observable macroscopic properties
|
ocsenave@0
|
238 settle down to a steady condition, after which no further changes
|
ocsenave@0
|
239 are seen unless there is a new intervention from the outside.
|
ocsenave@0
|
240 When this steady condition is reached, the experimentalist says
|
ocsenave@0
|
241 that the objects have reached a state of /equilibrium/ with each
|
ocsenave@0
|
242 other. Once again, more precise definitions of this term will
|
ocsenave@0
|
243 be needed eventually, but they require concepts not yet developed.
|
ocsenave@0
|
244 In any event, the criterion just stated is almost the only one
|
ocsenave@0
|
245 used in actual laboratory practice to decide when equilibrium
|
ocsenave@0
|
246 has been reached.
|
ocsenave@0
|
247
|
ocsenave@0
|
248
|
ocsenave@0
|
249 A particular case of equilibrium is encountered when we
|
ocsenave@0
|
250 place a thermometer in contact with another body. The reading
|
ocsenave@0
|
251 \(t\) of the thermometer may vary at first, but eventually it reach es
|
ocsenave@0
|
252 a steady value. Now the number \(t\) read by a thermometer is always.
|
ocsenave@0
|
253 by definition, the empirical temperature /of the thermometer/ (more
|
ocsenave@0
|
254 precisely, of the sensitive element of the thermometer). When
|
ocsenave@0
|
255 this number is constant in time, we say that the thermometer is
|
ocsenave@0
|
256 in /thermal equilibrium/ with its surroundings; and we then extend
|
ocsenave@0
|
257 the notion of temperature, calling the steady value \(t\) also the
|
ocsenave@0
|
258 /temperature of the surroundings/.
|
ocsenave@0
|
259
|
ocsenave@0
|
260 We have repeated these elementary facts, well known to every
|
ocsenave@0
|
261 child, in order to emphasize this point: Thermodynamics can be
|
ocsenave@0
|
262 a theory /only/ of states of equilibrium, because the very
|
ocsenave@0
|
263 procedure by which the temperature of a system is defined by
|
ocsenave@0
|
264 operational means, already presupposes the attainment of
|
ocsenave@0
|
265 equilibrium. Strictly speaking, therefore, classical
|
ocsenave@0
|
266 thermodynamics does not even contain the concept of a
|
ocsenave@0
|
267 \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
268
|
ocsenave@0
|
269 Of course, to recognize this limitation on conventional
|
ocsenave@0
|
270 thermodynamics (best emphasized by calling it instead,
|
ocsenave@0
|
271 thermostatics) in no way rules out the possibility of
|
ocsenave@0
|
272 generalizing the notion of temperature to nonequilibrium states.
|
ocsenave@0
|
273 Indeed, it is clear that one could define any number of
|
ocsenave@0
|
274 time-dependent quantities all of which reduce, in the special
|
ocsenave@0
|
275 case of equilibrium, to the temperature as defined above.
|
ocsenave@0
|
276 Historically, attempts to do this even antedated the discovery
|
ocsenave@0
|
277 of the laws of thermodynamics, as is demonstrated by
|
ocsenave@0
|
278 \ldquo{}Newton's law of cooling.\rdquo{} Therefore, the
|
ocsenave@0
|
279 question is not whether generalization is /possible/, but only
|
ocsenave@0
|
280 whether it is in any way /useful/; i.e., does the temperature so
|
ocsenave@0
|
281 generalized have any connection with other physical properties
|
ocsenave@0
|
282 of our system, so that it could help us to predict other things?
|
ocsenave@0
|
283 However, to raise such questions takes us far beyond the
|
ocsenave@0
|
284 domain of thermostatics; and the general laws of nonequilibrium
|
ocsenave@0
|
285 behavior are so much more complicated that it would be virtually
|
ocsenave@0
|
286 hopeless to try to unravel them by empirical means alone. For
|
ocsenave@0
|
287 example, even if two different kinds of thermometer are calibrated
|
ocsenave@0
|
288 so that they agree with each other in equilibrium situations,
|
ocsenave@0
|
289 they will not agree in general about the momentary value a
|
ocsenave@0
|
290 \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} To make any real
|
ocsenave@0
|
291 progress in this area, we have to supplement empirical observation by the guidance
|
ocsenave@0
|
292 of a rather hiqhly-developed theory. The notion of a
|
ocsenave@0
|
293 time-dependent temperature is far from simple conceptually, and we
|
ocsenave@0
|
294 will find that nothing very helpful can be said about this until
|
ocsenave@0
|
295 the full mathematical apparatus of nonequilibrium statistical
|
ocsenave@0
|
296 mechanics has been developed.
|
ocsenave@0
|
297
|
ocsenave@0
|
298 Suppose now that two bodies have the same temperature; i.e.,
|
ocsenave@0
|
299 a given thermometer reads the same steady value when in contact
|
ocsenave@0
|
300 with either. In order that the statement, \ldquo{}two bodies have the
|
ocsenave@1
|
301 same temperature\rdquo{} shall describe a physical property of the bodies,
|
ocsenave@0
|
302 and not merely an accidental circumstance due to our having used
|
ocsenave@0
|
303 a particular kind of thermometer, it is necessary that /all/
|
ocsenave@0
|
304 thermometers agree in assigning equal temperatures to them if
|
ocsenave@0
|
305 /any/ thermometer does . Only experiment is competent to determine
|
ocsenave@0
|
306 whether this universality property is true. Unfortunately, the
|
ocsenave@0
|
307 writer must confess that he is unable to cite any definite
|
ocsenave@0
|
308 experiment in which this point was subjected to a careful test.
|
ocsenave@0
|
309 That equality of temperatures has this absolute meaning, has
|
ocsenave@0
|
310 evidently been taken for granted so much that (like absolute
|
ocsenave@0
|
311 sirnultaneity in pre-relativity physics) most of us are not even
|
ocsenave@0
|
312 consciously aware that we make such an assumption in
|
ocsenave@0
|
313 thermodynamics. However, for the present we can only take it as a familiar
|
ocsenave@0
|
314 empirical fact that this condition does hold, not because we can
|
ocsenave@0
|
315 cite positive evidence for it, but because of the absence of
|
ocsenave@0
|
316 negative evidence against it; i.e., we think that, if an
|
ocsenave@0
|
317 exception had ever been found, this would have created a sensation in
|
ocsenave@0
|
318 physics, and we should have heard of it.
|
ocsenave@0
|
319
|
ocsenave@0
|
320 We now ask: when two bodies are at the same temperature,
|
ocsenave@0
|
321 are they then in thermal equilibrium with each other? Again,
|
ocsenave@0
|
322 only experiment is competent to answer this; the general
|
ocsenave@0
|
323 conclusion, again supported more by absence of negative evidence
|
ocsenave@0
|
324 than by specific positive evidence, is that the relation of
|
ocsenave@0
|
325 equilibrium has this property:
|
ocsenave@0
|
326 #+begin_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
327 /Two bodies in thermal equilibrium
|
ocsenave@0
|
328 with a third body, are thermal equilibrium with each other./
|
ocsenave@0
|
329 #+end_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
330
|
ocsenave@0
|
331 This empirical fact is usually called the \ldquo{}zero'th law of
|
ocsenave@0
|
332 thermodynamics.\rdquo{} Since nothing prevents us from regarding a
|
ocsenave@0
|
333 thermometer as the \ldquo{}third body\rdquo{} in the above statement,
|
ocsenave@0
|
334 it appears that we may also state the zero'th law as:
|
ocsenave@0
|
335 #+begin_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
336 /Two bodies are in thermal equilibrium with each other when they are
|
ocsenave@0
|
337 at the same temperature./
|
ocsenave@0
|
338 #+end_quote
|
ocsenave@0
|
339 Although from the preceding discussion it might appear that
|
ocsenave@0
|
340 these two statements of the zero'th law are entirely equivalent
|
ocsenave@0
|
341 (and we certainly have no empirical evidence against either), it
|
ocsenave@0
|
342 is interesting to note that there are theoretical reasons, arising
|
ocsenave@0
|
343 from General Relativity, indicating that while the first
|
ocsenave@0
|
344 statement may be universally valid, the second is not. When we
|
ocsenave@0
|
345 consider equilibrium in a gravitational field, the verification
|
ocsenave@0
|
346 that two bodies have equal temperatures may require transport
|
ocsenave@0
|
347 of the thermometer through a gravitational potential difference;
|
ocsenave@0
|
348 and this introduces a new element into the discussion. We will
|
ocsenave@0
|
349 consider this in more detail in a later Chapter, and show that
|
ocsenave@0
|
350 according to General Relativity, equilibrium in a large system
|
ocsenave@0
|
351 requires, not that the temperature be uniform at all points, but
|
ocsenave@0
|
352 rather that a particular function of temperature and gravitational
|
ocsenave@0
|
353 potential be constant (the function is \(T\cdot \exp{(\Phi/c^2})\), where
|
ocsenave@0
|
354 \(T\) is the Kelvin temperature to be defined later, and \(\Phi\) is the
|
ocsenave@0
|
355 gravitational potential).
|
ocsenave@0
|
356
|
ocsenave@0
|
357 Of course, this effect is so small that ordinary terrestrial
|
ocsenave@0
|
358 experiments would need to have a precision many orders of
|
ocsenave@0
|
359 magnitude beyond that presently possible, before one could hope even
|
ocsenave@0
|
360 to detect it; and needless to say, it has played no role in the
|
ocsenave@0
|
361 development of thermodynamics. For present purposes, therefore,
|
ocsenave@0
|
362 we need not distinguish between the two above statements of the
|
ocsenave@0
|
363 zero'th law, and we take it as a basic empirical fact that a
|
ocsenave@0
|
364 uniform temperature at all points of a system is an essential
|
ocsenave@0
|
365 condition for equilibrium. It is an important part of our
|
ocsenave@0
|
366 ivestigation to determine whether there are other essential
|
ocsenave@0
|
367 conditions as well. In fact, as we will find, there are many
|
ocsenave@0
|
368 different kinds of equilibrium; and failure to distinguish between
|
ocsenave@0
|
369 them can be a prolific source of paradoxes.
|
ocsenave@0
|
370
|
ocsenave@0
|
371 ** Equation of State
|
ocsenave@0
|
372 Another important reproducible connection is found when
|
ocsenave@0
|
373 we consider a thermodynamic system defined by
|
ocsenave@0
|
374 three parameters; in addition to the temperature we choose a
|
ocsenave@0
|
375 \ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{} and a conjugate \ldquo{}force.\rdquo{}
|
ocsenave@0
|
376 Subject to some qualifications given below, we find experimentally
|
ocsenave@0
|
377 that these parameters are not independent, but are subject to a constraint.
|
ocsenave@0
|
378 For example, we cannot vary the equilibrium pressure, volume,
|
ocsenave@0
|
379 and temperature of a given mass of gas independently; it is found
|
ocsenave@0
|
380 that a given pressure and volume can be realized only at one
|
ocsenave@0
|
381 particular temperature, that the gas will assume a given tempera~
|
ocsenave@0
|
382 ture and volume only at one particular pressure, etc. Similarly,
|
ocsenave@0
|
383 a stretched wire can be made to have arbitrarily assigned tension
|
ocsenave@0
|
384 and elongation only if its temperature is suitably chosen, a
|
ocsenave@0
|
385 dielectric will assume a state of given temperature and
|
ocsenave@0
|
386 polarization at only one value of the electric field, etc.
|
ocsenave@0
|
387 These simplest nontrivial thermodynamic systems (three
|
ocsenave@0
|
388 parameters with one constraint) are said to possess two
|
ocsenave@0
|
389 /degrees of freedom/; for the range of possible equilibrium states is defined
|
ocsenave@0
|
390 by specifying any two of the variables arbitrarily, whereupon the
|
ocsenave@0
|
391 third, and all others we may introduce, are determined.
|
ocsenave@0
|
392 Mathematically, this is expressed by the existence of a functional
|
ocsenave@1
|
393 relationship of the form[fn:: /Edit./: The set of solutions to an equation
|
ocsenave@0
|
394 like /f(X,x,t)=/ const. is called a /level set/. Here, Jaynes is
|
ocsenave@0
|
395 saying that the quantities /X/, /x/, and /t/ follow a \ldquo{}functional
|
ocsenave@0
|
396 rule\rdquo{}, so the set of physically allowed combinations of /X/,
|
ocsenave@0
|
397 /x/, and /t/ in equilibrium states can be
|
ocsenave@0
|
398 expressed as the level set of a function.
|
ocsenave@0
|
399
|
ocsenave@0
|
400 But not every function expresses a constraint relation; for some
|
ocsenave@0
|
401 functions, you can specify two of the variables, and the third will
|
ocsenave@0
|
402 still be undetermined. (For example, if f=X^2+x^2+t^2-3,
|
ocsenave@0
|
403 the level set /f(X,x,t)=0/ is a sphere, and specifying /x=1/, /t=1/
|
ocsenave@0
|
404 leaves you with two potential possibilities for /X/ =\pm 1.)
|
ocsenave@0
|
405
|
ocsenave@1
|
406 A function like /f/ has to possess one more propery in order for its
|
ocsenave@1
|
407 level set to express a constraint relationship: it must be monotonic in
|
ocsenave@0
|
408 each of its variables /X/, /x/, and /t/.
|
ocsenave@0
|
409 #the partial derivatives of /f/ exist for every allowed combination of
|
ocsenave@0
|
410 #inputs /x/, /X/, and /t/.
|
ocsenave@0
|
411 In other words, the level set has to pass a sort of
|
ocsenave@0
|
412 \ldquo{}vertical line test\rdquo{} for each of its variables.]
|
ocsenave@0
|
413
|
ocsenave@0
|
414 #Edit Here, Jaynes
|
ocsenave@0
|
415 #is saying that it is possible to express the collection of allowed combinations \(\langle X,x,t \rangle\) of force, quantity, and temperature as a
|
ocsenave@0
|
416 #[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_set][level set]] of some function \(f\). However, not all level sets represent constraint relations; consider \(f(X,x,t)=X^2+x^2+t^2-1\)=0.
|
ocsenave@0
|
417 #In order to specify
|
ocsenave@0
|
418
|
ocsenave@0
|
419 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
420 f(X,x,t) = O
|
ocsenave@0
|
421 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
422
|
ocsenave@0
|
423 where $X$ is a generalized force (pressure, tension, electric or
|
ocsenave@0
|
424 magnetic field, etc.), $x$ is the corresponding generalized
|
ocsenave@0
|
425 displacement (volume, elongation, electric or magnetic polarization,
|
ocsenave@1
|
426 etc.), and $t$ is the empirical temperature. Equation (1-1) is
|
ocsenave@0
|
427 called /the equation of state/.
|
ocsenave@0
|
428
|
ocsenave@0
|
429 At the risk of belaboring it, we emphasize once again that
|
ocsenave@0
|
430 all of this applies only for a system in equilibrium; for
|
ocsenave@0
|
431 otherwise not only.the temperature, but also some or all of the other
|
ocsenave@0
|
432 variables may not be definable. For example, no unique pressure
|
ocsenave@0
|
433 can be assigned to a gas which has just suffered a sudden change
|
ocsenave@0
|
434 in volume, until the generated sound waves have died out.
|
ocsenave@0
|
435
|
ocsenave@0
|
436 Independently of its functional form, the mere fact of the
|
ocsenave@0
|
437 /existence/ of an equation of state has certain experimental
|
ocsenave@0
|
438 consequences. For example, suppose that in experiments on oxygen
|
ocsenave@0
|
439 gas, in which we control the temperature and pressure
|
ocsenave@0
|
440 independently, we have found that the isothermal compressibility $K$
|
ocsenave@0
|
441 varies with temperature, and the thermal expansion coefficient
|
ocsenave@0
|
442 \alpha varies with pressure $P$, so that within the accuracy of the data,
|
ocsenave@0
|
443
|
ocsenave@0
|
444 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
445 \frac{\partial K}{\partial t} = - \frac{\partial \alpha}{\partial P}
|
ocsenave@0
|
446 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
447
|
ocsenave@0
|
448 Is this a particular property of oxygen; or is there reason to
|
ocsenave@0
|
449 believe that it holds also for other substances? Does it depend
|
ocsenave@0
|
450 on our particular choice of a temperature scale?
|
ocsenave@0
|
451
|
ocsenave@0
|
452 In this case, the answer is found at once; for the definitions of $K$,
|
ocsenave@0
|
453 \alpha are
|
ocsenave@0
|
454
|
ocsenave@0
|
455 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
456 K = -\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial P},\qquad
|
ocsenave@0
|
457 \alpha=\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial t}
|
ocsenave@0
|
458 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
459
|
ocsenave@0
|
460 which is simply a mathematical expression of the fact that the
|
ocsenave@0
|
461 volume $V$ is a definite function of $P$ and $t$; i.e., it depends
|
ocsenave@0
|
462 only
|
ocsenave@0
|
463 on their present values, and not how those values were attained.
|
ocsenave@0
|
464 In particular, $V$ does not depend on the direction in the \((P, t)\)
|
ocsenave@0
|
465 plane through which the present values were approached; or, as we
|
ocsenave@0
|
466 usually say it, \(dV\) is an /exact differential/.
|
ocsenave@0
|
467
|
ocsenave@1
|
468 Therefore, although at first glance the relation (1-2) appears
|
ocsenave@0
|
469 nontrivial and far from obvious, a trivial mathematical analysis
|
ocsenave@0
|
470 convinces us that it must hold regardless of our particular
|
ocsenave@0
|
471 temperature scale, and that it is true not only of oxygen; it must
|
ocsenave@0
|
472 hold for any substance, or mixture of substances, which possesses a
|
ocsenave@0
|
473 definite, reproducible equation of state \(f(P,V,t)=0\).
|
ocsenave@0
|
474
|
ocsenave@0
|
475 But this understanding also enables us to predict situations in which
|
ocsenave@1
|
476 (1-2) will /not/ hold. Equation (1-2), as we have just learned, expresses
|
ocsenave@0
|
477 the fact that an equation of state exists involving only the three
|
ocsenave@0
|
478 variables \((P,V,t)\). Now suppose we try to apply it to a liquid such
|
ocsenave@0
|
479 as nitrobenzene. The nitrobenzene molecule has a large electric dipole
|
ocsenave@0
|
480 moment; and so application of an electric field (as in the
|
ocsenave@0
|
481 [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kerr_effect][electro-optical Kerr cell]]) causes an alignment of molecules which, as
|
ocsenave@0
|
482 accurate measurements will verify, changes the pressure at a given
|
ocsenave@0
|
483 temperature and volume. Therefore, there can no longer exist any
|
ocsenave@0
|
484 unique equation of state involving \((P, V, t)\) only; with
|
ocsenave@0
|
485 sufficiently accurate measurements, nitrobenzene must be regarded as a
|
ocsenave@0
|
486 thermodynamic system with at least three degrees of freedom, and the
|
ocsenave@0
|
487 general equation of state must have at least a complicated a form as
|
ocsenave@0
|
488 \(f(P,V,t,E) = 0\).
|
ocsenave@0
|
489
|
ocsenave@0
|
490 But if we introduce a varying electric field $E$ into the discussion,
|
ocsenave@0
|
491 the resulting varying electric polarization $M$ also becomes a new
|
ocsenave@0
|
492 thermodynamic variable capable of being measured. Experimentally, it
|
ocsenave@0
|
493 is easiest to control temperature, pressure, and electric field
|
ocsenave@0
|
494 independently, and of course we find that both the volume and
|
ocsenave@0
|
495 polarization are then determined; i.e., there must exist functional
|
ocsenave@0
|
496 relations of the form \(V = V(P,t,E)\), \(M = M(P,t,E)\), or in more
|
ocsenave@0
|
497 symmetrical form
|
ocsenave@0
|
498
|
ocsenave@0
|
499 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
500 f(V,P,t,E) = 0 \qquad g(M,P,t,E)=0.
|
ocsenave@0
|
501 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
502
|
ocsenave@0
|
503 In other words, if we regard nitrobenzene as a thermodynamic system of
|
ocsenave@0
|
504 three degrees of freedom (i.e., having specified three parameters
|
ocsenave@0
|
505 arbitrarily, all others are then determined), it must possess two
|
ocsenave@0
|
506 independent equations of state.
|
ocsenave@0
|
507
|
ocsenave@0
|
508 Similarly, a thermodynamic system with four degrees of freedom,
|
ocsenave@0
|
509 defined by the termperature and three pairs of conjugate forces and
|
ocsenave@0
|
510 displacements, will have three independent equations of state, etc.
|
ocsenave@0
|
511
|
ocsenave@0
|
512 Now, returning to our original question, if nitrobenzene possesses
|
ocsenave@0
|
513 this extra electrical degree of freedom, under what circumstances do
|
ocsenave@0
|
514 we exprect to find a reproducible equation of state involving
|
ocsenave@0
|
515 \((p,V,t)\) only? Evidently, if $E$ is held constant, then the first
|
ocsenave@0
|
516 of equations (1-5) becomes such an equation of state, involving $E$ as
|
ocsenave@0
|
517 a fixed parameter; we would find many different equations of state of
|
ocsenave@0
|
518 the form \(f(P,V,t) = 0\) with a different function $f$ for each
|
ocsenave@0
|
519 different value of the electric field. Likewise, if \(M\) is held
|
ocsenave@0
|
520 constant, we can eliminate \(E\) between equations (1-5) and find a
|
ocsenave@0
|
521 relation \(h(P,V,t,M)=0\), which is an equation of state for
|
ocsenave@0
|
522 \((P,V,t)\) containing \(M\) as a fixed parameter.
|
ocsenave@0
|
523
|
ocsenave@0
|
524 More generally, if an electrical constraint is imposed on the system
|
ocsenave@0
|
525 (for example, by connecting an external charged capacitor to the
|
ocsenave@0
|
526 electrodes) so that \(M\) is determined by \(E\); i.e., there is a
|
ocsenave@0
|
527 functional relation of the form
|
ocsenave@0
|
528
|
ocsenave@0
|
529 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
530 g(M,E) = \text{const.}
|
ocsenave@0
|
531 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@0
|
532
|
ocsenave@0
|
533 then (1-5) and (1-6) constitute three simultaneous equations, from
|
ocsenave@0
|
534 which both \(E\) and \(M\) may be eliminated mathematically, leading
|
ocsenave@0
|
535 to a relation of the form \(h(P,V,t;q)=0\), which is an equation of
|
ocsenave@0
|
536 state for \((P,V,t)\) involving the fixed parameter \(q\).
|
ocsenave@0
|
537
|
ocsenave@0
|
538 We see, then, that as long as a fixed constraint of the form (1-6) is
|
ocsenave@0
|
539 imposed on the electrical degree of freedom, we can still observe a
|
ocsenave@0
|
540 reproducible equation of state for nitrobenzene, considered as a
|
ocsenave@0
|
541 thermodynamic system of only two degrees of freedom. If, however, this
|
ocsenave@0
|
542 electrical constraint is removed, so that as we vary $P$ and $t$, the
|
ocsenave@0
|
543 values of $E$ and $M$ vary in an uncontrolled way over a
|
ocsenave@0
|
544 /two-dimensional/ region of the \((E, M)\) plane, then we will find no
|
ocsenave@0
|
545 definite equation of state involving only \((P,V,t)\).
|
ocsenave@0
|
546
|
ocsenave@0
|
547 This may be stated more colloqually as follows: even though a system
|
ocsenave@0
|
548 has three degrees of freedom, we can still consider only the variables
|
ocsenave@0
|
549 belonging to two of them, and we will find a definite equation of
|
ocsenave@0
|
550 state, /provided/ that in the course of the experiments, the unused
|
ocsenave@0
|
551 degree of freedom is not \ldquo{}tampered with\rdquo{} in an
|
ocsenave@0
|
552 uncontrolled way.
|
ocsenave@0
|
553
|
ocsenave@0
|
554 We have already emphasized that any physical system corresponds to
|
ocsenave@0
|
555 many different thermodynamic systems, depending on which variables we
|
ocsenave@0
|
556 choose to control and measure. In fact, it is easy to see that any
|
ocsenave@0
|
557 physical system has, for all practical purposes, an /arbitrarily
|
ocsenave@0
|
558 large/ number of degrees of freedom. In the case of nitrobenzene, for
|
ocsenave@0
|
559 example, we may impose any variety of nonuniform electric fields on
|
ocsenave@1
|
560 our sample. Suppose we place $(n+1)$ different electrodes, labelled
|
ocsenave@1
|
561 \(\{e_0,e_1, e_2 \ldots e_n\}\) in contact with the liquid in various
|
ocsenave@1
|
562 positions. Regarding \(e_0\) as the \ldquo{}ground\rdquo{}, maintained
|
ocsenave@1
|
563 at zero potential, we can then impose $n$ different potentials
|
ocsenave@1
|
564 \(\{v_1, \ldots, v_n\}\) on the other electrodes independently, and we
|
ocsenave@1
|
565 can also measure the $n$ different conjugate displacements, as the
|
ocsenave@1
|
566 charges \(\{q_1,\ldots, q_n\}\) accumulated on electrodes
|
ocsenave@1
|
567 \(\{e_1,\ldots e_n\}\). Together with the pressure (understood as the
|
ocsenave@1
|
568 pressure measured at one given position), volume, and temperature, our
|
ocsenave@1
|
569 sample of nitrobenzene is now a thermodynamic system of $(n+1)$
|
ocsenave@1
|
570 degrees of freedom. This number may be as large as we please, limited
|
ocsenave@1
|
571 only by our patience in constructing the apparatus needed to control
|
ocsenave@1
|
572 or measure all these quantities.
|
ocsenave@1
|
573
|
ocsenave@1
|
574 We leave it as an exercise for the reader (Problem 1) to find the most
|
ocsenave@1
|
575 general condition on the variables \(\{v_1, q_1, v_2, q_2, \ldots
|
ocsenave@1
|
576 v_n,q_n\}\) which will ensure that a definite equation of state
|
ocsenave@1
|
577 $f(P,V,t)=0$ is observed in spite of all these new degrees of
|
ocsenave@1
|
578 freedom. The simplest special case of this relation is, evidently, to
|
ocsenave@1
|
579 ground all electrodes, thereby inposing the conditions $v_1 = v_2 =
|
ocsenave@1
|
580 \ldots = v_n = 0$. Equally well (if we regard nitrobenzene as having
|
ocsenave@1
|
581 negligible electrical conductivity) we may open-circuit all
|
ocsenave@1
|
582 electrodes, thereby imposing the conditions \(q_i = \text{const.}\) In
|
ocsenave@1
|
583 the latter case, in addition to an equation of state of the form
|
ocsenave@1
|
584 \(f(P,V,t)=0\), which contains these constants as fixed parameters,
|
ocsenave@1
|
585 there are \(n\) additional equations of state of the form $v_i =
|
ocsenave@1
|
586 v_i(P,t)$. But if we choose to ignore these voltages, there will be no
|
ocsenave@1
|
587 contradiction in considering our nitrobenzene to be a thermodynamic
|
ocsenave@1
|
588 system of two degrees of freedom, involving only the variables
|
ocsenave@1
|
589 \(P,V,t\).
|
ocsenave@1
|
590
|
ocsenave@1
|
591 Similarly, if our system of interest is a crystal, we may impose on it
|
ocsenave@1
|
592 a wide variety of nonuniform stress fields; each component of the
|
ocsenave@1
|
593 stress tensor $T_{ij}$ may bary with position. We might expand each of
|
ocsenave@1
|
594 these functions in a complete orthonormal set of functions
|
ocsenave@1
|
595 \(\phi_k(x,y,z)\):
|
ocsenave@1
|
596
|
ocsenave@1
|
597 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@1
|
598 T_{ij}(x,y,z) = \sum_k a_{ijk} \phi_k(x,y,z)
|
ocsenave@1
|
599 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@1
|
600
|
ocsenave@1
|
601 and with a sufficiently complicated system of levers which in various
|
ocsenave@1
|
602 ways squeeze and twist the crystal, we might vary each of the first
|
ocsenave@1
|
603 1,000 expansion coefficients $a_{ijk}$ independently, and measure the
|
ocsenave@1
|
604 conjugate displacements $q_{ijk}$. Our crystal is then a thermodynamic
|
ocsenave@1
|
605 system of over 1,000 degrees of freedom.
|
ocsenave@1
|
606
|
ocsenave@1
|
607 The notion of \ldquo{}numbers of degrees of freedom\rdquo{} is
|
ocsenave@1
|
608 therefore not a /physical property/ of any system; it is entirely
|
ocsenave@1
|
609 anthropomorphic, since any physical system may be regarded as a
|
ocsenave@1
|
610 thermodynamic system with any number of degrees of freedom we please.
|
ocsenave@1
|
611
|
ocsenave@1
|
612 If new thermodynamic variables are always introduced in pairs,
|
ocsenave@1
|
613 consisting of a \ldquo{}force\rdquo{} and conjugate
|
ocsenave@1
|
614 \ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{}, then a thermodynamic system of $n$
|
ocsenave@1
|
615 degrees of freedom must possess $(n-1)$ independent equations of
|
ocsenave@1
|
616 state, so that specifying $n$ quantities suffices to determine all
|
ocsenave@1
|
617 others.
|
ocsenave@1
|
618
|
ocsenave@1
|
619 This raises an interesting question; whether the scheme of classifying
|
ocsenave@1
|
620 thermodynamic variables in conjugate pairs is the most general
|
ocsenave@1
|
621 one. Why, for example, is it not natural to introduce three related
|
ocsenave@1
|
622 variables at a time? To the best of the writer's knowledge, this is an
|
ocsenave@1
|
623 open question; there seems to be no fundamental reason why variables
|
ocsenave@1
|
624 /must/ always be introduced in conjugate pairs, but there seems to be
|
ocsenave@1
|
625 no known case in which a different scheme suggests itself as more
|
ocsenave@1
|
626 appropriate.
|
ocsenave@1
|
627
|
ocsenave@1
|
628 ** Heat
|
ocsenave@1
|
629 We are now in a position to consider the results and interpretation of
|
ocsenave@1
|
630 a number of elementary experiments involving
|
ocsenave@2
|
631 thermal interaction, which can be carried out as soon as a primitive
|
ocsenave@2
|
632 thermometer is at hand. In fact these experiments, which we summarize
|
ocsenave@2
|
633 so quickly, required a very long time for their first performance, and
|
ocsenave@2
|
634 the essential conclusions of this Section were first arrived at only
|
ocsenave@2
|
635 about 1760---more than 160 years after Galileo's invention of the
|
ocsenave@2
|
636 thermometer---by Joseph Black, who was Professor of Chemistry at
|
ocsenave@2
|
637 Glasgow University. Black's analysis of calorimetric experiments
|
ocsenave@2
|
638 initiated by G. D. Fahrenheit before 1736 led to the first recognition
|
ocsenave@2
|
639 of the distinction between temperature and heat, and prepared the way
|
ocsenave@2
|
640 for the work of his better-known pupil, James Watt.
|
ocsenave@1
|
641
|
ocsenave@2
|
642 We first observe that if two bodies at different temperatures are
|
ocsenave@2
|
643 separated by walls of various materials, they sometimes maintain their
|
ocsenave@2
|
644 temperature difference for a long time, and sometimes reach thermal
|
ocsenave@2
|
645 equilibrium very quickly. The differences in behavior observed must be
|
ocsenave@2
|
646 ascribed to the different properties of the separating walls, since
|
ocsenave@2
|
647 nothing else is changed. Materials such as wood, asbestos, porous
|
ocsenave@2
|
648 ceramics (and most of all, modern porous plastics like styrofoam), are
|
ocsenave@2
|
649 able to sustain a temperature difference for a long time; a wall of an
|
ocsenave@2
|
650 imaginary material with this property idealized to the point where a
|
ocsenave@2
|
651 temperature difference is maintained indefinitely is called an
|
ocsenave@2
|
652 /adiabatic wall/. A very close approximation to a perfect adiabatic
|
ocsenave@2
|
653 wall is realized by the Dewar flask (thermos bottle), of which the
|
ocsenave@2
|
654 walls consist of two layers of glass separated by a vacuum, with the
|
ocsenave@2
|
655 surfaces silvered like a mirror. In such a container, as we all know,
|
ocsenave@2
|
656 liquids may be maintained hot or cold for days.
|
ocsenave@1
|
657
|
ocsenave@2
|
658 On the other hand, a thin wall of copper or silver is hardly able to
|
ocsenave@2
|
659 sustain any temperature difference at all; two bodies separated by
|
ocsenave@2
|
660 such a partition come to thermal equilibrium very quickly. Such a wall
|
ocsenave@2
|
661 is called /diathermic/. It is found in general that the best
|
ocsenave@2
|
662 diathermic materials are the metals and good electrical conductors,
|
ocsenave@2
|
663 while electrical insulators make fairly good adiabatic walls. There
|
ocsenave@2
|
664 are good theoretical reasons for this rule; a particular case of it is
|
ocsenave@2
|
665 given by the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wiedemann_franz_law][Wiedemann-Franz law]] of solid-state theory.
|
ocsenave@2
|
666
|
ocsenave@2
|
667 Since a body surrounded by an adiabatic wall is able to maintain its
|
ocsenave@2
|
668 temperature independently of the temperature of its surroundings, an
|
ocsenave@2
|
669 adiabatic wall provides a means of thermally /isolating/ a system from
|
ocsenave@2
|
670 the rest of the universe; it is to be expected, therefore, that the
|
ocsenave@2
|
671 laws of thermal interaction between two systems will assume the
|
ocsenave@2
|
672 simplest form if they are enclosed in a common adiabatic container,
|
ocsenave@2
|
673 and that the best way of carrying out experiments on thermal
|
ocsenave@2
|
674 peroperties of substances is to so enclose them. Such an apparatus, in
|
ocsenave@2
|
675 which systems are made to interact inside an adiabatic container
|
ocsenave@2
|
676 supplied with a thermometer, is called a /calorimeter/.
|
ocsenave@2
|
677
|
ocsenave@2
|
678 Let us imagine that we have a calorimeter in which there is initially
|
ocsenave@2
|
679 a volume $V_W$ of water at a temperature $t_1$, and suspended above it
|
ocsenave@2
|
680 a volume $V_I$ of some other substance (say, iron) at temperature
|
ocsenave@2
|
681 $t_2$. When we drop the iron into the water, they interact thermally
|
ocsenave@2
|
682 (and the exact nature of this interaction is one of the things we hope
|
ocsenave@2
|
683 to learn now), the temperature of both changing until they are in
|
ocsenave@2
|
684 thermal equilibrium at a final temperature $t_0$.
|
ocsenave@2
|
685
|
ocsenave@2
|
686 Now we repeat the experiment with different initial temperatures
|
ocsenave@2
|
687 $t_1^\prime$ and $t_2^\prime$, so that a new equilibrium is reached at
|
ocsenave@2
|
688 temperature $t_0^\prime$. It is found that, if the temperature
|
ocsenave@2
|
689 differences are sufficiently small (and in practice this is not a
|
ocsenave@2
|
690 serious limitation if we use a mercury thermometer calibrated with
|
ocsenave@2
|
691 uniformly spaced degree marks on a capillary of uniform bore), then
|
ocsenave@2
|
692 whatever the values of $t_1^\prime$, $t_2^\prime$, $t_1$, $t_2$, the
|
ocsenave@2
|
693 final temperatures $t_0^\prime$, $t_0$ will adjust themselves so that
|
ocsenave@2
|
694 the following relation holds:
|
ocsenave@2
|
695
|
ocsenave@2
|
696 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
697 \frac{t_2 - t_0}{t_0 - t_1} = \frac{t_2^\prime -
|
ocsenave@2
|
698 t_0^\prime}{t_0^\prime - t_1^\prime}
|
ocsenave@2
|
699 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
700
|
ocsenave@2
|
701 in other words, the /ratio/ of the temperature changes of the iron and
|
ocsenave@2
|
702 water is independent of the initial temperatures used.
|
ocsenave@2
|
703
|
ocsenave@2
|
704 We now vary the amounts of iron and water used in the calorimeter. It
|
ocsenave@2
|
705 is found that the ratio (1-8), although always independent of the
|
ocsenave@2
|
706 starting temperatures, does depend on the relative amounts of iron and
|
ocsenave@2
|
707 water. It is, in fact, proportional to the mass $M_W$ of water and
|
ocsenave@2
|
708 inversely proportional to the mass $M_I$ of iron, so that
|
ocsenave@2
|
709
|
ocsenave@2
|
710 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
711 \frac{t_2-t_0}{t_0-t_1} = \frac{M_W}{K_I M_I}
|
ocsenave@2
|
712 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
713
|
ocsenave@2
|
714 where $K_I$ is a constant.
|
ocsenave@2
|
715
|
ocsenave@2
|
716 We next repeat the above experiments using a different material in
|
ocsenave@2
|
717 place of the iron (say, copper). We find again a relation
|
ocsenave@2
|
718
|
ocsenave@2
|
719 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
720 \frac{t_2-t_0}{t_0-t_1} = \frac{M_W}{K_C \cdot M_C}
|
ocsenave@2
|
721 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
722
|
ocsenave@2
|
723 where $M_C$ is the mass of copper; but the constant $K_C$ is different
|
ocsenave@2
|
724 from the previous $K_I$. In fact, we see that the constant $K_I$ is a
|
ocsenave@2
|
725 new physical property of the substance iron, while $K_C$ is a physical
|
ocsenave@2
|
726 property of copper. The number $K$ is called the /specific heat/ of a
|
ocsenave@2
|
727 substance, and it is seen that according to this definition, the
|
ocsenave@2
|
728 specific heat of water is unity.
|
ocsenave@2
|
729
|
ocsenave@2
|
730 We now have enough experimental facts to begin speculating about their
|
ocsenave@2
|
731 interpretation, as was first done in the 18th century. First, note
|
ocsenave@2
|
732 that equation (1-9) can be put into a neater form that is symmetrical
|
ocsenave@2
|
733 between the two substances. We write $\Delta t_I = t_0 - t_2$, $\Delta
|
ocsenave@2
|
734 t_W = t_0 - t_1$ for the temperature changes of iron and water
|
ocsenave@2
|
735 respectively, and define $K_W \equiv 1$ for water. Equation (1-9) then
|
ocsenave@2
|
736 becomes
|
ocsenave@2
|
737
|
ocsenave@2
|
738 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
739 K_W M_W \Delta t_W + K_I M_I \Delta t_I = 0
|
ocsenave@2
|
740 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
741
|
ocsenave@2
|
742 The form of this equation suggests a new experiment; we go back into
|
ocsenave@2
|
743 the laboratory, and find $n$ substances for which the specific heats
|
ocsenave@2
|
744 \(\{K_1,\ldots K_n\}\) have been measured previously. Taking masses
|
ocsenave@2
|
745 \(\{M_1, \ldots, M_n\}\) of these substances, we heat them to $n$
|
ocsenave@2
|
746 different temperatures \(\{t_1,\ldots, t_n\}\) and throw them all into
|
ocsenave@2
|
747 the calorimeter at once. After they have all come to thermal
|
ocsenave@2
|
748 equilibrium at temperature $t_0$, we find the differences $\Delta t_j
|
ocsenave@2
|
749 = t_0 - t_j$. Just as we suspected, it turns out that regardless of
|
ocsenave@2
|
750 the $K$'s, $M$'s, and $t$'s chosen, the relation
|
ocsenave@2
|
751 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
752 \sum_{j=0}^n K_j M_j \Delta t_j = 0
|
ocsenave@2
|
753 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
754 is always satisfied. This sort of process is an old story in
|
ocsenave@2
|
755 scientific investigations; although the great theoretician Boltzmann
|
ocsenave@2
|
756 is said to have remarked: \ldquo{}Elegance is for tailors \rdquo{}, it
|
ocsenave@2
|
757 remains true that the attempt to reduce equations to the most
|
ocsenave@2
|
758 symmetrical form has often suggested important generalizations of
|
ocsenave@2
|
759 physical laws, and is a great aid to memory. Witness Maxwell's
|
ocsenave@2
|
760 \ldquo{}displacement current\rdquo{}, which was needed to fill in a
|
ocsenave@2
|
761 gap and restore the symmetry of the electromagnetic equations; as soon
|
ocsenave@2
|
762 as it was put in, the equations predicted the existence of
|
ocsenave@2
|
763 electromagnetic waves. In the present case, the search for a rather
|
ocsenave@2
|
764 rudimentary form of \ldquo{}elegance\rdquo{} has also been fruitful,
|
ocsenave@2
|
765 for we recognize that (1-12) has the standard form of a /conservation
|
ocsenave@2
|
766 law/; it defines a new quantity which is conserved in thermal
|
ocsenave@2
|
767 interactions of the type just studied.
|
ocsenave@2
|
768
|
ocsenave@2
|
769 The similarity of (1-12) to conservation laws in general may be seen
|
ocsenave@2
|
770 as follows. Let $A$ be some quantity that is conserved; the $i$th
|
ocsenave@2
|
771 system has an amount of it $A_i$. Now when the systems interact such
|
ocsenave@2
|
772 that some $A$ is transferred between them, the amount of $A$ in the
|
ocsenave@2
|
773 $i$th system is changed by a net amount \(\Delta A_i = (A_i)_{final} -
|
ocsenave@2
|
774 (A_i)_{initial}\); and the fact that there is no net change in the
|
ocsenave@2
|
775 total amount of $A$ is expressed by the equation \(\sum_i \Delta
|
ocsenave@2
|
776 A_i = 0$. Thus, the law of conservation of matter in a chemical
|
ocsenave@2
|
777 reaction is expressed by \(\sum_i \Delta M_i = 0\), where $M_i$ is the
|
ocsenave@2
|
778 mass of the $i$th chemical component.
|
ocsenave@2
|
779
|
ocsenave@2
|
780 what is this new conserved quantity? Mathematically, it can be defined
|
ocsenave@2
|
781 as $Q_i = K_i\cdot M_i cdot t_i; whereupon (1-12) becomes
|
ocsenave@2
|
782
|
ocsenave@2
|
783 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
784 \sum_i \Delta Q_i = 0
|
ocsenave@2
|
785 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
786
|
ocsenave@2
|
787 and at this point we can correct a slight quantitative inaccuracy. As
|
ocsenave@2
|
788 noted, the above relations hold accurately only when the temperature
|
ocsenave@2
|
789 differences are sufficiently small; i.e., they are really only
|
ocsenave@2
|
790 differential laws. On sufficiently accurate measurements one find that
|
ocsenave@2
|
791 the specific heats $K_i$ depend on temperature; if we then adopt the
|
ocsenave@2
|
792 integral definition of $\Delta Q_i$,
|
ocsenave@2
|
793 \begin{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
794 \Delta Q_i = \int_{t_{i}}^{t_0} K_i(t) M_i dt
|
ocsenave@2
|
795 \end{equation}
|
ocsenave@2
|
796
|
ocsenave@2
|
797 the conservation law (1-13) will be found to hold in calorimetric
|
ocsenave@2
|
798 experiments with liquids and solids, to any accuracy now feasible. And
|
ocsenave@2
|
799 of course, from the manner in which the $K_i(t)$ are defined, this
|
ocsenave@2
|
800 relation will hold however our thermometers are calibrated.
|
ocsenave@2
|
801
|
ocsenave@2
|
802 Evidently, the stage is now set for a \ldquo{}new\rdquo{} physical
|
ocsenave@2
|
803 theory to account for these facts. In the 17th century, both Francis
|
ocsenave@2
|
804 Bacon and Isaac Newton had expressed their opinions that heat was a
|
ocsenave@2
|
805 form of motion; but they had no supporting factual evidence. By the
|
ocsenave@2
|
806 latter part of the 18th century, one had definite factual evidence
|
ocsenave@2
|
807 which seemed to make this view untenable; by the calorimetric
|
ocsenave@2
|
808 \ldquo{}mixing\rdquo{} experiments just described, Joseph Black had
|
ocsenave@2
|
809 recognized the distinction between temperature $t$ as a measure of
|
ocsenave@2
|
810 \ldquo{}hotness\rdquo{}, and heat $Q$ as a measure of /quantity/ of
|
ocsenave@2
|
811 something, and introduced the notion of heat capacity. He also
|
ocsenave@2
|
812 recognized the latent heats of freezing and vaporization. To account
|
ocsenave@2
|
813 for the conservation laws thus discovered, the theory then suggested
|
ocsenave@2
|
814 itself, naturally and almost inevitably, that heat was /fluid/,
|
ocsenave@2
|
815 indestructable and uncreatable, which had no appreciable weight and
|
ocsenave@2
|
816 was attracted differently by different kinds of matter. In 1787,
|
ocsenave@2
|
817 Lavoisier invented the name \ldquo{}caloric\rdquo{} for this fluid.
|
ocsenave@2
|
818
|
ocsenave@2
|
819 Looking down today from our position of superior knowledge (i.e.,
|
ocsenave@2
|
820 hindsight) we perhaps need to be reminded that the caloric theory was
|
ocsenave@2
|
821 a perfectly respectable scientific theory, fully deserving of serious
|
ocsenave@2
|
822 consideration; for it accounted quantitatively for a large body of
|
ocsenave@2
|
823 experimental fact, and made new predictions capable of being tested by
|
ocsenave@2
|
824 experiment.
|
ocsenave@2
|
825
|
ocsenave@2
|
826 One of these predictions was the possibility of accounting for the
|
ocsenave@2
|
827 thermal expansion of bodies when heated; perhaps the increase in
|
ocsenave@2
|
828 volume was just a measure of the volume of caloric fluid
|
ocsenave@2
|
829 absorbed. This view met with some disappointment as a result of
|
ocsenave@2
|
830 experiments which showed that different materials, on absorbing the
|
ocsenave@2
|
831 same quantity of heat, expanded by different amounts. Of course, this
|
ocsenave@2
|
832 in itself was not enough to overthrow the caloric theory, because one
|
ocsenave@2
|
833 could suppose that the caloric fluid was compressible, and was held
|
ocsenave@2
|
834 under different pressure in different media.
|
ocsenave@2
|
835
|
ocsenave@2
|
836 Another difficulty that seemed increasingly serious by the end of the
|
ocsenave@2
|
837 18th century was the failure of all attempts to weigh this fluid. Many
|
ocsenave@2
|
838 careful experiments were carried out, by Boyle, Fordyce, Rumford and
|
ocsenave@2
|
839 others (and continued by Landolt almost into the 20th century), with
|
ocsenave@2
|
840 balances capable of detecting a change of weight of one part in a
|
ocsenave@2
|
841 million; and no change could be detected on the melting of ice,
|
ocsenave@2
|
842 heating of substances, or carrying out of chemical reactions. But even
|
ocsenave@2
|
843 this is not really a conclusive argument against the caloric theory,
|
ocsenave@2
|
844 since there is no /a priori/ reason why the fluid should be dense
|
ocsenave@2
|
845 enough to weigh with balances (of course, we know today from
|
ocsenave@2
|
846 Einstein's $E=mc^2$ that small changes in weight should indeed exist
|
ocsenave@2
|
847 in these experiments; but to measure them would require balances about
|
ocsenave@2
|
848 10^7 times more sensitive than were available).
|
ocsenave@2
|
849
|
ocsenave@2
|
850 Since the caloric theory derives entirely from the empirical
|
ocsenave@2
|
851 conservation law (1-33), it can be refuted conclusively only by
|
ocsenave@2
|
852 exhibiting new experimental facts revealing situations in which (1-13)
|
ocsenave@2
|
853 is /not/ valid. The first such case was [[http://www.chemteam.info/Chem-History/Rumford-1798.html][found by Count Rumford (1798)]],
|
ocsenave@2
|
854 who was in charge of boring cannon in the Munich arsenal, and noted
|
ocsenave@2
|
855 that the cannon and chips became hot as a result of the cutting. He
|
ocsenave@2
|
856 found that heat could be produced indefinitely, as long as the boring
|
ocsenave@2
|
857 was continued, without any compensating cooling of any other part of
|
ocsenave@2
|
858 the system. Here, then, was a clear case in which caloric was /not/
|
ocsenave@2
|
859 conserved, as in (1-13); but could be created at will. Rumford wrote
|
ocsenave@2
|
860 that he could not conceive of anything that could be produced
|
ocsenave@2
|
861 indefinitely by the expenditure of work, \ldquo{}except it be /motion/\rdquo{}.
|
ocsenave@2
|
862
|
ocsenave@2
|
863 But even this was not enough to cause abandonment of the caloric
|
ocsenave@2
|
864 theory; for while Rumford's observations accomplished the negative
|
ocsenave@2
|
865 purpose of showing that the conservation law (1-13) is not universally
|
ocsenave@2
|
866 valid, they failed to accomplish the positive one of showing what
|
ocsenave@2
|
867 specific law should replace it (although he produced a good hint, not
|
ocsenave@2
|
868 sufficiently appreciated at the time, in his crude measurements of the
|
ocsenave@2
|
869 rate of heat production due to the work of one horse). Within the
|
ocsenave@2
|
870 range of the original calorimetric experiments, (1-13) was still
|
ocsenave@2
|
871 valid, and a theory successful in a restricted domain is better than
|
ocsenave@2
|
872 no theory at all; so Rumford's work had very little impact on the
|
ocsenave@2
|
873 actual development of thermodynamics.
|
ocsenave@2
|
874
|
ocsenave@2
|
875 (This situation is a recurrent one in science, and today physics offers
|
ocsenave@2
|
876 another good example. It is recognized by all that our present quantum
|
ocsenave@2
|
877 field theory is unsatisfactory on logical, conceptual, and
|
ocsenave@2
|
878 mathematical grounds; yet it also contains some important truth, and
|
ocsenave@2
|
879 no responsible person has suggested that it be abandoned. Once again,
|
ocsenave@2
|
880 a semi-satisfactory theory is better than none at all, and we will
|
ocsenave@2
|
881 continue to teach it and to use it until we have something better to
|
ocsenave@2
|
882 put in its place.)
|
ocsenave@2
|
883
|
ocsenave@2
|
884 # what is "the specific heat of a gas at constant pressure/volume"?
|
ocsenave@2
|
885 # changed t for temperature below from capital T to lowercase t.
|
ocsenave@2
|
886 Another failure of the conservation law (1-13) was noted in 1842 by
|
ocsenave@2
|
887 R. Mayer, a German physician, who pointed out that the data already
|
ocsenave@2
|
888 available showed that the specific heat of a gas at constant pressure,
|
ocsenave@2
|
889 C_p, was greater than at constant volume $C_v$. He surmised that the
|
ocsenave@2
|
890 difference was due to the work done in expansion of the gas against
|
ocsenave@2
|
891 atmospheric pressure, when measuring $C_p$. Supposing that the
|
ocsenave@2
|
892 difference $\Delta Q = (C_p - C_v)\Delta t$ calories, in the heat
|
ocsenave@2
|
893 required to raise the temperature by $\Delta t$ was actually a
|
ocsenave@2
|
894 measure of amount of energy, he could estimate from the amount
|
ocsenave@2
|
895 $P\Delta V$ ergs of work done the amount of mechanical energy (number
|
ocsenave@2
|
896 of ergs) corresponding to a calorie of heat; but again his work had
|
ocsenave@2
|
897 very little impact on the development of thermodynamics, because he
|
ocsenave@2
|
898 merely offered this notion as an interpretation of the data without
|
ocsenave@2
|
899 performing or suggesting any new experiments to check his hypothesis
|
ocsenave@2
|
900 further.
|
ocsenave@2
|
901
|
ocsenave@2
|
902 Up to the point, then, one has the experimental fact that a
|
ocsenave@2
|
903 conservation law (1-13) exists whenever purely thermal interactions
|
ocsenave@2
|
904 were involved; but in processes involving mechanical work, the
|
ocsenave@2
|
905 conservation law broke down.
|
ocsenave@2
|
906
|
ocsenave@2
|
907 ** The First Law
|
ocsenave@2
|
908
|
ocsenave@2
|
909
|
ocsenave@2
|
910
|
ocsenave@2
|
911 * COMMENT Appendix
|
ocsenave@1
|
912
|
ocsenave@1
|
913 | Generalized Force | Generalized Displacement |
|
ocsenave@1
|
914 |--------------------+--------------------------|
|
ocsenave@1
|
915 | force | displacement |
|
ocsenave@1
|
916 | pressure | volume |
|
ocsenave@1
|
917 | electric potential | charge |
|