Mercurial > jaynes
comparison org/stat-mech.org @ 2:afbe1fe19b36
Transcribed up to section 1.6, the first law.
author | Dylan Holmes <ocsenave@gmail.com> |
---|---|
date | Sat, 28 Apr 2012 23:06:48 -0500 |
parents | 4da2176e4890 |
children | 8f3b6dcb9add |
comparison
equal
deleted
inserted
replaced
1:4da2176e4890 | 2:afbe1fe19b36 |
---|---|
626 appropriate. | 626 appropriate. |
627 | 627 |
628 ** Heat | 628 ** Heat |
629 We are now in a position to consider the results and interpretation of | 629 We are now in a position to consider the results and interpretation of |
630 a number of elementary experiments involving | 630 a number of elementary experiments involving |
631 | 631 thermal interaction, which can be carried out as soon as a primitive |
632 | 632 thermometer is at hand. In fact these experiments, which we summarize |
633 * Appendix | 633 so quickly, required a very long time for their first performance, and |
634 the essential conclusions of this Section were first arrived at only | |
635 about 1760---more than 160 years after Galileo's invention of the | |
636 thermometer---by Joseph Black, who was Professor of Chemistry at | |
637 Glasgow University. Black's analysis of calorimetric experiments | |
638 initiated by G. D. Fahrenheit before 1736 led to the first recognition | |
639 of the distinction between temperature and heat, and prepared the way | |
640 for the work of his better-known pupil, James Watt. | |
641 | |
642 We first observe that if two bodies at different temperatures are | |
643 separated by walls of various materials, they sometimes maintain their | |
644 temperature difference for a long time, and sometimes reach thermal | |
645 equilibrium very quickly. The differences in behavior observed must be | |
646 ascribed to the different properties of the separating walls, since | |
647 nothing else is changed. Materials such as wood, asbestos, porous | |
648 ceramics (and most of all, modern porous plastics like styrofoam), are | |
649 able to sustain a temperature difference for a long time; a wall of an | |
650 imaginary material with this property idealized to the point where a | |
651 temperature difference is maintained indefinitely is called an | |
652 /adiabatic wall/. A very close approximation to a perfect adiabatic | |
653 wall is realized by the Dewar flask (thermos bottle), of which the | |
654 walls consist of two layers of glass separated by a vacuum, with the | |
655 surfaces silvered like a mirror. In such a container, as we all know, | |
656 liquids may be maintained hot or cold for days. | |
657 | |
658 On the other hand, a thin wall of copper or silver is hardly able to | |
659 sustain any temperature difference at all; two bodies separated by | |
660 such a partition come to thermal equilibrium very quickly. Such a wall | |
661 is called /diathermic/. It is found in general that the best | |
662 diathermic materials are the metals and good electrical conductors, | |
663 while electrical insulators make fairly good adiabatic walls. There | |
664 are good theoretical reasons for this rule; a particular case of it is | |
665 given by the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wiedemann_franz_law][Wiedemann-Franz law]] of solid-state theory. | |
666 | |
667 Since a body surrounded by an adiabatic wall is able to maintain its | |
668 temperature independently of the temperature of its surroundings, an | |
669 adiabatic wall provides a means of thermally /isolating/ a system from | |
670 the rest of the universe; it is to be expected, therefore, that the | |
671 laws of thermal interaction between two systems will assume the | |
672 simplest form if they are enclosed in a common adiabatic container, | |
673 and that the best way of carrying out experiments on thermal | |
674 peroperties of substances is to so enclose them. Such an apparatus, in | |
675 which systems are made to interact inside an adiabatic container | |
676 supplied with a thermometer, is called a /calorimeter/. | |
677 | |
678 Let us imagine that we have a calorimeter in which there is initially | |
679 a volume $V_W$ of water at a temperature $t_1$, and suspended above it | |
680 a volume $V_I$ of some other substance (say, iron) at temperature | |
681 $t_2$. When we drop the iron into the water, they interact thermally | |
682 (and the exact nature of this interaction is one of the things we hope | |
683 to learn now), the temperature of both changing until they are in | |
684 thermal equilibrium at a final temperature $t_0$. | |
685 | |
686 Now we repeat the experiment with different initial temperatures | |
687 $t_1^\prime$ and $t_2^\prime$, so that a new equilibrium is reached at | |
688 temperature $t_0^\prime$. It is found that, if the temperature | |
689 differences are sufficiently small (and in practice this is not a | |
690 serious limitation if we use a mercury thermometer calibrated with | |
691 uniformly spaced degree marks on a capillary of uniform bore), then | |
692 whatever the values of $t_1^\prime$, $t_2^\prime$, $t_1$, $t_2$, the | |
693 final temperatures $t_0^\prime$, $t_0$ will adjust themselves so that | |
694 the following relation holds: | |
695 | |
696 \begin{equation} | |
697 \frac{t_2 - t_0}{t_0 - t_1} = \frac{t_2^\prime - | |
698 t_0^\prime}{t_0^\prime - t_1^\prime} | |
699 \end{equation} | |
700 | |
701 in other words, the /ratio/ of the temperature changes of the iron and | |
702 water is independent of the initial temperatures used. | |
703 | |
704 We now vary the amounts of iron and water used in the calorimeter. It | |
705 is found that the ratio (1-8), although always independent of the | |
706 starting temperatures, does depend on the relative amounts of iron and | |
707 water. It is, in fact, proportional to the mass $M_W$ of water and | |
708 inversely proportional to the mass $M_I$ of iron, so that | |
709 | |
710 \begin{equation} | |
711 \frac{t_2-t_0}{t_0-t_1} = \frac{M_W}{K_I M_I} | |
712 \end{equation} | |
713 | |
714 where $K_I$ is a constant. | |
715 | |
716 We next repeat the above experiments using a different material in | |
717 place of the iron (say, copper). We find again a relation | |
718 | |
719 \begin{equation} | |
720 \frac{t_2-t_0}{t_0-t_1} = \frac{M_W}{K_C \cdot M_C} | |
721 \end{equation} | |
722 | |
723 where $M_C$ is the mass of copper; but the constant $K_C$ is different | |
724 from the previous $K_I$. In fact, we see that the constant $K_I$ is a | |
725 new physical property of the substance iron, while $K_C$ is a physical | |
726 property of copper. The number $K$ is called the /specific heat/ of a | |
727 substance, and it is seen that according to this definition, the | |
728 specific heat of water is unity. | |
729 | |
730 We now have enough experimental facts to begin speculating about their | |
731 interpretation, as was first done in the 18th century. First, note | |
732 that equation (1-9) can be put into a neater form that is symmetrical | |
733 between the two substances. We write $\Delta t_I = t_0 - t_2$, $\Delta | |
734 t_W = t_0 - t_1$ for the temperature changes of iron and water | |
735 respectively, and define $K_W \equiv 1$ for water. Equation (1-9) then | |
736 becomes | |
737 | |
738 \begin{equation} | |
739 K_W M_W \Delta t_W + K_I M_I \Delta t_I = 0 | |
740 \end{equation} | |
741 | |
742 The form of this equation suggests a new experiment; we go back into | |
743 the laboratory, and find $n$ substances for which the specific heats | |
744 \(\{K_1,\ldots K_n\}\) have been measured previously. Taking masses | |
745 \(\{M_1, \ldots, M_n\}\) of these substances, we heat them to $n$ | |
746 different temperatures \(\{t_1,\ldots, t_n\}\) and throw them all into | |
747 the calorimeter at once. After they have all come to thermal | |
748 equilibrium at temperature $t_0$, we find the differences $\Delta t_j | |
749 = t_0 - t_j$. Just as we suspected, it turns out that regardless of | |
750 the $K$'s, $M$'s, and $t$'s chosen, the relation | |
751 \begin{equation} | |
752 \sum_{j=0}^n K_j M_j \Delta t_j = 0 | |
753 \end{equation} | |
754 is always satisfied. This sort of process is an old story in | |
755 scientific investigations; although the great theoretician Boltzmann | |
756 is said to have remarked: \ldquo{}Elegance is for tailors \rdquo{}, it | |
757 remains true that the attempt to reduce equations to the most | |
758 symmetrical form has often suggested important generalizations of | |
759 physical laws, and is a great aid to memory. Witness Maxwell's | |
760 \ldquo{}displacement current\rdquo{}, which was needed to fill in a | |
761 gap and restore the symmetry of the electromagnetic equations; as soon | |
762 as it was put in, the equations predicted the existence of | |
763 electromagnetic waves. In the present case, the search for a rather | |
764 rudimentary form of \ldquo{}elegance\rdquo{} has also been fruitful, | |
765 for we recognize that (1-12) has the standard form of a /conservation | |
766 law/; it defines a new quantity which is conserved in thermal | |
767 interactions of the type just studied. | |
768 | |
769 The similarity of (1-12) to conservation laws in general may be seen | |
770 as follows. Let $A$ be some quantity that is conserved; the $i$th | |
771 system has an amount of it $A_i$. Now when the systems interact such | |
772 that some $A$ is transferred between them, the amount of $A$ in the | |
773 $i$th system is changed by a net amount \(\Delta A_i = (A_i)_{final} - | |
774 (A_i)_{initial}\); and the fact that there is no net change in the | |
775 total amount of $A$ is expressed by the equation \(\sum_i \Delta | |
776 A_i = 0$. Thus, the law of conservation of matter in a chemical | |
777 reaction is expressed by \(\sum_i \Delta M_i = 0\), where $M_i$ is the | |
778 mass of the $i$th chemical component. | |
779 | |
780 what is this new conserved quantity? Mathematically, it can be defined | |
781 as $Q_i = K_i\cdot M_i cdot t_i; whereupon (1-12) becomes | |
782 | |
783 \begin{equation} | |
784 \sum_i \Delta Q_i = 0 | |
785 \end{equation} | |
786 | |
787 and at this point we can correct a slight quantitative inaccuracy. As | |
788 noted, the above relations hold accurately only when the temperature | |
789 differences are sufficiently small; i.e., they are really only | |
790 differential laws. On sufficiently accurate measurements one find that | |
791 the specific heats $K_i$ depend on temperature; if we then adopt the | |
792 integral definition of $\Delta Q_i$, | |
793 \begin{equation} | |
794 \Delta Q_i = \int_{t_{i}}^{t_0} K_i(t) M_i dt | |
795 \end{equation} | |
796 | |
797 the conservation law (1-13) will be found to hold in calorimetric | |
798 experiments with liquids and solids, to any accuracy now feasible. And | |
799 of course, from the manner in which the $K_i(t)$ are defined, this | |
800 relation will hold however our thermometers are calibrated. | |
801 | |
802 Evidently, the stage is now set for a \ldquo{}new\rdquo{} physical | |
803 theory to account for these facts. In the 17th century, both Francis | |
804 Bacon and Isaac Newton had expressed their opinions that heat was a | |
805 form of motion; but they had no supporting factual evidence. By the | |
806 latter part of the 18th century, one had definite factual evidence | |
807 which seemed to make this view untenable; by the calorimetric | |
808 \ldquo{}mixing\rdquo{} experiments just described, Joseph Black had | |
809 recognized the distinction between temperature $t$ as a measure of | |
810 \ldquo{}hotness\rdquo{}, and heat $Q$ as a measure of /quantity/ of | |
811 something, and introduced the notion of heat capacity. He also | |
812 recognized the latent heats of freezing and vaporization. To account | |
813 for the conservation laws thus discovered, the theory then suggested | |
814 itself, naturally and almost inevitably, that heat was /fluid/, | |
815 indestructable and uncreatable, which had no appreciable weight and | |
816 was attracted differently by different kinds of matter. In 1787, | |
817 Lavoisier invented the name \ldquo{}caloric\rdquo{} for this fluid. | |
818 | |
819 Looking down today from our position of superior knowledge (i.e., | |
820 hindsight) we perhaps need to be reminded that the caloric theory was | |
821 a perfectly respectable scientific theory, fully deserving of serious | |
822 consideration; for it accounted quantitatively for a large body of | |
823 experimental fact, and made new predictions capable of being tested by | |
824 experiment. | |
825 | |
826 One of these predictions was the possibility of accounting for the | |
827 thermal expansion of bodies when heated; perhaps the increase in | |
828 volume was just a measure of the volume of caloric fluid | |
829 absorbed. This view met with some disappointment as a result of | |
830 experiments which showed that different materials, on absorbing the | |
831 same quantity of heat, expanded by different amounts. Of course, this | |
832 in itself was not enough to overthrow the caloric theory, because one | |
833 could suppose that the caloric fluid was compressible, and was held | |
834 under different pressure in different media. | |
835 | |
836 Another difficulty that seemed increasingly serious by the end of the | |
837 18th century was the failure of all attempts to weigh this fluid. Many | |
838 careful experiments were carried out, by Boyle, Fordyce, Rumford and | |
839 others (and continued by Landolt almost into the 20th century), with | |
840 balances capable of detecting a change of weight of one part in a | |
841 million; and no change could be detected on the melting of ice, | |
842 heating of substances, or carrying out of chemical reactions. But even | |
843 this is not really a conclusive argument against the caloric theory, | |
844 since there is no /a priori/ reason why the fluid should be dense | |
845 enough to weigh with balances (of course, we know today from | |
846 Einstein's $E=mc^2$ that small changes in weight should indeed exist | |
847 in these experiments; but to measure them would require balances about | |
848 10^7 times more sensitive than were available). | |
849 | |
850 Since the caloric theory derives entirely from the empirical | |
851 conservation law (1-33), it can be refuted conclusively only by | |
852 exhibiting new experimental facts revealing situations in which (1-13) | |
853 is /not/ valid. The first such case was [[http://www.chemteam.info/Chem-History/Rumford-1798.html][found by Count Rumford (1798)]], | |
854 who was in charge of boring cannon in the Munich arsenal, and noted | |
855 that the cannon and chips became hot as a result of the cutting. He | |
856 found that heat could be produced indefinitely, as long as the boring | |
857 was continued, without any compensating cooling of any other part of | |
858 the system. Here, then, was a clear case in which caloric was /not/ | |
859 conserved, as in (1-13); but could be created at will. Rumford wrote | |
860 that he could not conceive of anything that could be produced | |
861 indefinitely by the expenditure of work, \ldquo{}except it be /motion/\rdquo{}. | |
862 | |
863 But even this was not enough to cause abandonment of the caloric | |
864 theory; for while Rumford's observations accomplished the negative | |
865 purpose of showing that the conservation law (1-13) is not universally | |
866 valid, they failed to accomplish the positive one of showing what | |
867 specific law should replace it (although he produced a good hint, not | |
868 sufficiently appreciated at the time, in his crude measurements of the | |
869 rate of heat production due to the work of one horse). Within the | |
870 range of the original calorimetric experiments, (1-13) was still | |
871 valid, and a theory successful in a restricted domain is better than | |
872 no theory at all; so Rumford's work had very little impact on the | |
873 actual development of thermodynamics. | |
874 | |
875 (This situation is a recurrent one in science, and today physics offers | |
876 another good example. It is recognized by all that our present quantum | |
877 field theory is unsatisfactory on logical, conceptual, and | |
878 mathematical grounds; yet it also contains some important truth, and | |
879 no responsible person has suggested that it be abandoned. Once again, | |
880 a semi-satisfactory theory is better than none at all, and we will | |
881 continue to teach it and to use it until we have something better to | |
882 put in its place.) | |
883 | |
884 # what is "the specific heat of a gas at constant pressure/volume"? | |
885 # changed t for temperature below from capital T to lowercase t. | |
886 Another failure of the conservation law (1-13) was noted in 1842 by | |
887 R. Mayer, a German physician, who pointed out that the data already | |
888 available showed that the specific heat of a gas at constant pressure, | |
889 C_p, was greater than at constant volume $C_v$. He surmised that the | |
890 difference was due to the work done in expansion of the gas against | |
891 atmospheric pressure, when measuring $C_p$. Supposing that the | |
892 difference $\Delta Q = (C_p - C_v)\Delta t$ calories, in the heat | |
893 required to raise the temperature by $\Delta t$ was actually a | |
894 measure of amount of energy, he could estimate from the amount | |
895 $P\Delta V$ ergs of work done the amount of mechanical energy (number | |
896 of ergs) corresponding to a calorie of heat; but again his work had | |
897 very little impact on the development of thermodynamics, because he | |
898 merely offered this notion as an interpretation of the data without | |
899 performing or suggesting any new experiments to check his hypothesis | |
900 further. | |
901 | |
902 Up to the point, then, one has the experimental fact that a | |
903 conservation law (1-13) exists whenever purely thermal interactions | |
904 were involved; but in processes involving mechanical work, the | |
905 conservation law broke down. | |
906 | |
907 ** The First Law | |
908 | |
909 | |
910 | |
911 * COMMENT Appendix | |
634 | 912 |
635 | Generalized Force | Generalized Displacement | | 913 | Generalized Force | Generalized Displacement | |
636 |--------------------+--------------------------| | 914 |--------------------+--------------------------| |
637 | force | displacement | | 915 | force | displacement | |
638 | pressure | volume | | 916 | pressure | volume | |