Mercurial > jaynes
changeset 0:26acdaf2e8c7
beginit begins.
author | Dylan Holmes <ocsenave@gmail.com> |
---|---|
date | Sat, 28 Apr 2012 19:32:50 -0500 |
parents | |
children | 4da2176e4890 |
files | org/stat-mech.org sources/stat.mech.1.pdf sources/stat.mech.2.pdf sources/stat.mech.5.pdf |
diffstat | 4 files changed, 560 insertions(+), 0 deletions(-) [+] |
line wrap: on
line diff
1.1 --- /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 1.2 +++ b/org/stat-mech.org Sat Apr 28 19:32:50 2012 -0500 1.3 @@ -0,0 +1,560 @@ 1.4 +#+TITLE: Statistical Mechanics 1.5 +#+AUTHOR: E.T. Jaynes; edited by Dylan Holmes 1.6 +#+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu 1.7 +#+KEYWORDS: statistical mechanics, thermostatics, thermodynamics, temperature, paradoxes, Jaynes 1.8 +#+SETUPFILE: ../../aurellem/org/setup.org 1.9 +#+INCLUDE: ../../aurellem/org/level-0.org 1.10 +#+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"http://www.aurellem.org/MathJax/MathJax.js" 1.11 + 1.12 +# "extensions/eqn-number.js" 1.13 + 1.14 +#+begin_quote 1.15 +*Note:* The following is a typeset version of 1.16 + [[../sources/stat.mech.1.pdf][this unpublished book draft]], written by [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Edwin_Thompson_Jaynes][E.T. Jaynes]]. I have only made 1.17 + minor changes, e.g. to correct typographical errors, add references, or format equations. The 1.18 + content itself is intact. --- Dylan 1.19 +#+end_quote 1.20 + 1.21 +* Development of Thermodynamics 1.22 +Our first intuitive, or \ldquo{}subjective\rdquo{} notions of temperature 1.23 +arise from the sensations of warmth and cold associated with our 1.24 +sense of touch . Yet science has been able to convert this qualitative 1.25 +sensation into an accurately defined quantitative notion, 1.26 +which can be applied far beyond the range of our direct experience. 1.27 +Today an experimentalist will report confidently that his 1.28 +spin system was at a temperature of 2.51 degrees Kelvin; and a 1.29 +theoretician will report with almost as much confidence that the 1.30 +temperature at the center of the sun is about \(2 \times 10^7\) degrees 1.31 +Kelvin. 1.32 + 1.33 +The /fact/ that this has proved possible, and the main technical 1.34 +ideas involved, are assumed already known to the reader; 1.35 +and we are not concerned here with repeating standard material 1.36 +already available in a dozen other textbooks . However 1.37 +thermodynamics, in spite of its great successes, firmly established 1.38 +for over a century, has also produced a great deal of confusion 1.39 +and a long list of \ldquo{}paradoxes\rdquo{} centering mostly 1.40 +around the second law and the nature of irreversibility. 1.41 +For this reason and others noted below, we want to dwell here at 1.42 +some length on the /logic/ underlying the development of 1.43 +thermodynamics . Our aim is to emphasize certain points which, 1.44 +in the writer's opinion, are essential for clearing up the 1.45 +confusion and resolving the paradoxes; but which are not 1.46 +sufficiently ernphasized---and indeed in many cases are 1.47 +totally ignored---in other textbooks. 1.48 + 1.49 +This attention to logic 1.50 +would not be particularly needed if we regarded classical 1.51 +thermodynamics (or, as it is becoming called increasingly, 1.52 +/thermostatics/) as a closed subject, in which the fundamentals 1.53 +are already completely established, and there is 1.54 +nothing more to be learned about them. A person who believes 1.55 +this will probably prefer a pure axiomatic approach, in which 1.56 +the basic laws are simply stated as arbitrary axioms, without 1.57 +any attempt to present the evidence for them; and one proceeds 1.58 +directly to working out their consequences. 1.59 +However, we take the attitude here that thermostatics, for 1.60 +all its venerable age, is very far from being a closed subject, 1.61 +we still have a great deal to learn about such matters as the 1.62 +most general definitions of equilibrium and reversibility, the 1.63 +exact range of validity of various statements of the second and 1.64 +third laws, the necessary and sufficient conditions for 1.65 +applicability of thermodynamics to special cases such as 1.66 +spin systems, and how thermodynamics can be applied to such 1.67 +systems as putty or polyethylene, which deform under force, 1.68 +but retain a \ldquo{}memory\rdquo{} of their past deformations. 1.69 +Is it possible to apply thermodynamics to a system such as a vibrating quartz crystal? We can by 1.70 +no means rule out the possibility that still more laws of 1.71 +thermodynamics exist, as yet undiscovered, which would be 1.72 +useful in such applications. 1.73 + 1.74 + 1.75 +It is only by careful examination of the logic by which 1.76 +present thermodynamics was created, asking exactly how much of 1.77 +it is mathematical theorems, how much is deducible from the laws 1.78 +of mechanics and electrodynamics, and how much rests only on 1.79 +empirical evidence, how compelling is present evidence for the 1.80 +accuracy and range of validity of its laws; in other words, 1.81 +exactly where are the boundaries of present knowledge, that we 1.82 +can hope to uncover new things. Clearly, much research is still 1.83 +needed in this field, and we shall be able to accomplish only a 1.84 +small part of this program in the present review. 1.85 + 1.86 + 1.87 +It will develop that there is an astonishingly close analogy 1.88 +with the logic underlying statistical theory in general, where 1.89 +again a qualitative feeling that we all have (for the degrees of 1.90 +plausibility of various unproved and undisproved assertions) must 1.91 +be convertefi into a precisely defined quantitative concept 1.92 +(probability). Our later development of probability theory in 1.93 +Chapter 6,7 will be, to a considerable degree, a paraphrase 1.94 +of our present review of the logic underlying classical 1.95 +thermodynamics. 1.96 + 1.97 +** The Primitive Thermometer. 1.98 + 1.99 +The earliest stages of our 1.100 +story are necessarily speculative, since they took place long 1.101 +before the beginnings of recorded history. But we can hardly 1.102 +doubt that primitive man learned quickly that objects exposed 1.103 +to the sun‘s rays or placed near a fire felt different from 1.104 +those in the shade away from fires; and the same difference was 1.105 +noted between animal bodies and inanimate objects. 1.106 + 1.107 + 1.108 +As soon as it was noted that changes in this feeling of 1.109 +warmth were correlated with other observable changes in the 1.110 +behavior of objects, such as the boiling and freezing of water, 1.111 +cooking of meat, melting of fat and wax, etc., the notion of 1.112 +warmth took its first step away from the purely subjective 1.113 +toward an objective, physical notion capable of being studied 1.114 +scientifically. 1.115 + 1.116 +One of the most striking manifestations of warmth (but far 1.117 +from the earliest discovered) is the almost universal expansion 1.118 +of gases, liquids, and solids when heated . This property has 1.119 +proved to be a convenient one with which to reduce the notion 1.120 +of warmth to something entirely objective. The invention of the 1.121 +/thermometer/, in which expansion of a mercury column, or a gas, 1.122 +or the bending of a bimetallic strip, etc. is read off on a 1.123 +suitable scale, thereby giving us a /number/ with which to work, 1.124 +was a necessary prelude to even the crudest study of the physical 1.125 +nature of heat. To the best of our knowledge, although the 1.126 +necessary technology to do this had been available for at least 1.127 +3,000 years, the first person to carry it out in practice was 1.128 +Galileo, in 1592. 1.129 + 1.130 +Later on we will give more precise definitions of the term 1.131 +\ldquo{}thermometer.\rdquo{} But at the present stage we 1.132 +are not in a position to do so (as Galileo was not), because 1.133 +the very concepts needed have not yet been developed; 1.134 +more precise definitions can be 1.135 +given only after our study has revealed the need for them. In 1.136 +deed, our final definition can be given only after the full 1.137 +mathematical formalism of statistical mechanics is at hand. 1.138 + 1.139 +Once a thermometer has been constructed, and the scale 1.140 +marked off in a quite arbitrary way (although we will suppose 1.141 +that the scale is at least monotonic: i.e., greater warmth always 1.142 +corresponds to a greater number), we are ready to begin scien 1.143 +tific experiments in thermodynamics. The number read eff from 1.144 +any such instrument is called the /empirical temperature/, and we 1.145 +denote it by \(t\). Since the exact calibration of the thermometer 1.146 +is not specified), any monotonic increasing function 1.147 +\(t‘ = f(t)\) provides an equally good temperature scale for the 1.148 +present. 1.149 + 1.150 + 1.151 +** Thermodynamic Systems. 1.152 + 1.153 +The \ldquo{}thermodynamic systems\rdquo{} which 1.154 +are the objects of our study may be, physically, almost any 1.155 +collections of objects. The traditional simplest system with 1.156 +which to begin a study of thermodynamics is a volume of gas. 1.157 +We shall, however, be concerned from the start also with such 1.158 +things as a stretched wire or membrane, an electric cell, a 1.159 +polarized dielectric, a paramagnetic body in a magnetic field, etc. 1.160 + 1.161 +The /thermodynamic state/ of such a system is determined by 1.162 +specifying (i.e., measuring) certain macrcoscopic physical 1.163 +properties. Now, any real physical system has many millions of such 1.164 +preperties; in order to have a usable theory we cannot require 1.165 +that /all/ of them be specified. We see, therefore, that there 1.166 +must be a clear distinction between the notions of 1.167 +\ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} and \ldquo{}physical 1.168 +system.\rdquo{} 1.169 +A given /physical/ system may correspond to many different 1.170 +/thermodynamic systems/, depending 1.171 +on which variables we choose to measure or control; and which 1.172 +we decide to leave unmeasured and/or uncontrolled. 1.173 + 1.174 + 1.175 +For example, our physical system might consist of a crystal 1.176 +of sodium chloride. For one set of experiments we work with 1.177 +temperature, volume, and pressure; and ignore its electrical 1.178 +properties. For another set of experiments we work with 1.179 +temperature, electric field, and electric polarization; and 1.180 +ignore the varying stress and strain. The /physical/ system, 1.181 +therefore, corresponds to two entirely different /thermodynamic/ 1.182 +systems. Exactly how much freedom, then, do we have in choosing 1.183 +the variables which shall define the thermodynamic state of our 1.184 +system? How many must we choose? What [criteria] determine when 1.185 +we have made an adequate choice? These questions cannot be 1.186 +answered until we say a little more about what we are trying to 1.187 +accomplish by a thermodynamic theory. A mere collection of 1.188 +recorded data about our system, as in the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CRC_Handbook_of_Chemistry_and_Physics][/Handbook of Physics and 1.189 +Chemistry/]], is a very useful thing, but it hardly constitutes 1.190 +a theory. In order to construct anything deserving of such a 1.191 +name, the primary requirement is that we can recognize some kind 1.192 +of reproducible connection between the different properties con 1.193 +sidered, so that information about some of them will enable us 1.194 +to predict others. And of course, in order that our theory can 1.195 +be called thermodynamics (and not some other area of physics), 1.196 +it is necessary that the temperature be one of the quantities 1.197 +involved in a nontrivial way. 1.198 + 1.199 +The gist of these remarks is that the notion of 1.200 +\ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} is in part 1.201 +an anthropomorphic one; it is for us to 1.202 +say which set of variables shall be used. If two different 1.203 +choices both lead to useful reproducible connections, it is quite 1.204 +meaningless to say that one choice is any more \ldquo{}correct\rdquo{} 1.205 +than the other. Recognition of this fact will prove crucial later in 1.206 +avoiding certain ancient paradoxes. 1.207 + 1.208 +At this stage we can determine only empirically which other 1.209 +physical properties need to be introduced before reproducible 1.210 +connections appear. Once any such connection is established, we 1.211 +can analyze it with the hope of being able to (1) reduce it to a 1.212 +/logical/ connection rather than an empirical one; and (2) extend 1.213 +it to an hypothesis applying beyond the original data, which 1.214 +enables us to predict further connections capable of being 1.215 +tested by experiment. Examples of this will be given presently. 1.216 + 1.217 + 1.218 +There will remain, however, a few reproducible relations 1.219 +which to the best of present knowledge, are not reducible to 1.220 +logical relations within the context of classical thermodynamics 1.221 +(and. whose demonstration in the wider context of mechanics, 1.222 +electrodynamics, and quantum theory remains one of probability 1.223 +rather than logical proof); from the standpoint of thermodynamics 1.224 +these remain simply statements of empirical fact which must be 1.225 +accepted as such without any deeper basis, but without which the 1.226 +development of thermodynamics cannot proceed. Because of this 1.227 +special status, these relations have become known as the 1.228 +\ldquo{}laws\rdquo{} 1.229 +of thermodynamics . The most fundamental one is a qualitative 1.230 +rather than quantitative relation, the \ldquo{}zero'th law.\rdquo{} 1.231 + 1.232 +** Equilibrium; the \ldquo{}Zero‘th Law.\rdquo{} 1.233 + 1.234 + It is a common experience 1.235 +that when objects are placed in contact with each other but 1.236 +isolated from their surroundings, they may undergo observable 1.237 +changes for a time as a result; one body may become warmer, 1.238 +another cooler, the pressure of a gas or volume of a liquid may 1.239 +change; stress or magnetization in a solid may change, etc. But 1.240 +after a sufficient time, the observable macroscopic properties 1.241 +settle down to a steady condition, after which no further changes 1.242 +are seen unless there is a new intervention from the outside. 1.243 +When this steady condition is reached, the experimentalist says 1.244 +that the objects have reached a state of /equilibrium/ with each 1.245 +other. Once again, more precise definitions of this term will 1.246 +be needed eventually, but they require concepts not yet developed. 1.247 +In any event, the criterion just stated is almost the only one 1.248 +used in actual laboratory practice to decide when equilibrium 1.249 +has been reached. 1.250 + 1.251 + 1.252 +A particular case of equilibrium is encountered when we 1.253 +place a thermometer in contact with another body. The reading 1.254 +\(t\) of the thermometer may vary at first, but eventually it reach es 1.255 +a steady value. Now the number \(t\) read by a thermometer is always. 1.256 +by definition, the empirical temperature /of the thermometer/ (more 1.257 +precisely, of the sensitive element of the thermometer). When 1.258 +this number is constant in time, we say that the thermometer is 1.259 +in /thermal equilibrium/ with its surroundings; and we then extend 1.260 +the notion of temperature, calling the steady value \(t\) also the 1.261 +/temperature of the surroundings/. 1.262 + 1.263 +We have repeated these elementary facts, well known to every 1.264 +child, in order to emphasize this point: Thermodynamics can be 1.265 +a theory /only/ of states of equilibrium, because the very 1.266 +procedure by which the temperature of a system is defined by 1.267 +operational means, already presupposes the attainment of 1.268 +equilibrium. Strictly speaking, therefore, classical 1.269 +thermodynamics does not even contain the concept of a 1.270 +\ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} 1.271 + 1.272 +Of course, to recognize this limitation on conventional 1.273 +thermodynamics (best emphasized by calling it instead, 1.274 +thermostatics) in no way rules out the possibility of 1.275 +generalizing the notion of temperature to nonequilibrium states. 1.276 +Indeed, it is clear that one could define any number of 1.277 +time-dependent quantities all of which reduce, in the special 1.278 +case of equilibrium, to the temperature as defined above. 1.279 +Historically, attempts to do this even antedated the discovery 1.280 +of the laws of thermodynamics, as is demonstrated by 1.281 +\ldquo{}Newton's law of cooling.\rdquo{} Therefore, the 1.282 +question is not whether generalization is /possible/, but only 1.283 +whether it is in any way /useful/; i.e., does the temperature so 1.284 +generalized have any connection with other physical properties 1.285 +of our system, so that it could help us to predict other things? 1.286 +However, to raise such questions takes us far beyond the 1.287 +domain of thermostatics; and the general laws of nonequilibrium 1.288 +behavior are so much more complicated that it would be virtually 1.289 +hopeless to try to unravel them by empirical means alone. For 1.290 +example, even if two different kinds of thermometer are calibrated 1.291 +so that they agree with each other in equilibrium situations, 1.292 +they will not agree in general about the momentary value a 1.293 +\ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} To make any real 1.294 +progress in this area, we have to supplement empirical observation by the guidance 1.295 +of a rather hiqhly-developed theory. The notion of a 1.296 +time-dependent temperature is far from simple conceptually, and we 1.297 +will find that nothing very helpful can be said about this until 1.298 +the full mathematical apparatus of nonequilibrium statistical 1.299 +mechanics has been developed. 1.300 + 1.301 +Suppose now that two bodies have the same temperature; i.e., 1.302 +a given thermometer reads the same steady value when in contact 1.303 +with either. In order that the statement, \ldquo{}two bodies have the 1.304 +same temperature\rdquo{} shall describe a physi cal property of the bodies, 1.305 +and not merely an accidental circumstance due to our having used 1.306 +a particular kind of thermometer, it is necessary that /all/ 1.307 +thermometers agree in assigning equal temperatures to them if 1.308 +/any/ thermometer does . Only experiment is competent to determine 1.309 +whether this universality property is true. Unfortunately, the 1.310 +writer must confess that he is unable to cite any definite 1.311 +experiment in which this point was subjected to a careful test. 1.312 +That equality of temperatures has this absolute meaning, has 1.313 +evidently been taken for granted so much that (like absolute 1.314 +sirnultaneity in pre-relativity physics) most of us are not even 1.315 +consciously aware that we make such an assumption in 1.316 +thermodynamics. However, for the present we can only take it as a familiar 1.317 +empirical fact that this condition does hold, not because we can 1.318 +cite positive evidence for it, but because of the absence of 1.319 +negative evidence against it; i.e., we think that, if an 1.320 +exception had ever been found, this would have created a sensation in 1.321 +physics, and we should have heard of it. 1.322 + 1.323 +We now ask: when two bodies are at the same temperature, 1.324 +are they then in thermal equilibrium with each other? Again, 1.325 +only experiment is competent to answer this; the general 1.326 +conclusion, again supported more by absence of negative evidence 1.327 +than by specific positive evidence, is that the relation of 1.328 +equilibrium has this property: 1.329 +#+begin_quote 1.330 +/Two bodies in thermal equilibrium 1.331 +with a third body, are thermal equilibrium with each other./ 1.332 +#+end_quote 1.333 + 1.334 +This empirical fact is usually called the \ldquo{}zero'th law of 1.335 +thermodynamics.\rdquo{} Since nothing prevents us from regarding a 1.336 +thermometer as the \ldquo{}third body\rdquo{} in the above statement, 1.337 +it appears that we may also state the zero'th law as: 1.338 +#+begin_quote 1.339 +/Two bodies are in thermal equilibrium with each other when they are 1.340 +at the same temperature./ 1.341 +#+end_quote 1.342 +Although from the preceding discussion it might appear that 1.343 +these two statements of the zero'th law are entirely equivalent 1.344 +(and we certainly have no empirical evidence against either), it 1.345 +is interesting to note that there are theoretical reasons, arising 1.346 +from General Relativity, indicating that while the first 1.347 +statement may be universally valid, the second is not. When we 1.348 +consider equilibrium in a gravitational field, the verification 1.349 +that two bodies have equal temperatures may require transport 1.350 +of the thermometer through a gravitational potential difference; 1.351 +and this introduces a new element into the discussion. We will 1.352 +consider this in more detail in a later Chapter, and show that 1.353 +according to General Relativity, equilibrium in a large system 1.354 +requires, not that the temperature be uniform at all points, but 1.355 +rather that a particular function of temperature and gravitational 1.356 +potential be constant (the function is \(T\cdot \exp{(\Phi/c^2})\), where 1.357 +\(T\) is the Kelvin temperature to be defined later, and \(\Phi\) is the 1.358 +gravitational potential). 1.359 + 1.360 +Of course, this effect is so small that ordinary terrestrial 1.361 +experiments would need to have a precision many orders of 1.362 +magnitude beyond that presently possible, before one could hope even 1.363 +to detect it; and needless to say, it has played no role in the 1.364 +development of thermodynamics. For present purposes, therefore, 1.365 +we need not distinguish between the two above statements of the 1.366 +zero'th law, and we take it as a basic empirical fact that a 1.367 +uniform temperature at all points of a system is an essential 1.368 +condition for equilibrium. It is an important part of our 1.369 +ivestigation to determine whether there are other essential 1.370 +conditions as well. In fact, as we will find, there are many 1.371 +different kinds of equilibrium; and failure to distinguish between 1.372 +them can be a prolific source of paradoxes. 1.373 + 1.374 +** Equation of State 1.375 +Another important reproducible connection is found when 1.376 +we consider a thermodynamic system defined by 1.377 +three parameters; in addition to the temperature we choose a 1.378 +\ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{} and a conjugate \ldquo{}force.\rdquo{} 1.379 +Subject to some qualifications given below, we find experimentally 1.380 +that these parameters are not independent, but are subject to a constraint. 1.381 +For example, we cannot vary the equilibrium pressure, volume, 1.382 +and temperature of a given mass of gas independently; it is found 1.383 +that a given pressure and volume can be realized only at one 1.384 +particular temperature, that the gas will assume a given tempera~ 1.385 +ture and volume only at one particular pressure, etc. Similarly, 1.386 +a stretched wire can be made to have arbitrarily assigned tension 1.387 +and elongation only if its temperature is suitably chosen, a 1.388 +dielectric will assume a state of given temperature and 1.389 +polarization at only one value of the electric field, etc. 1.390 +These simplest nontrivial thermodynamic systems (three 1.391 +parameters with one constraint) are said to possess two 1.392 +/degrees of freedom/; for the range of possible equilibrium states is defined 1.393 +by specifying any two of the variables arbitrarily, whereupon the 1.394 +third, and all others we may introduce, are determined. 1.395 +Mathematically, this is expressed by the existence of a functional 1.396 +relationship of the form[fn::Edit: The set of solutions to an equation 1.397 +like /f(X,x,t)=/ const. is called a /level set/. Here, Jaynes is 1.398 +saying that the quantities /X/, /x/, and /t/ follow a \ldquo{}functional 1.399 +rule\rdquo{}, so the set of physically allowed combinations of /X/, 1.400 +/x/, and /t/ in equilibrium states can be 1.401 +expressed as the level set of a function. 1.402 + 1.403 +But not every function expresses a constraint relation; for some 1.404 +functions, you can specify two of the variables, and the third will 1.405 +still be undetermined. (For example, if f=X^2+x^2+t^2-3, 1.406 +the level set /f(X,x,t)=0/ is a sphere, and specifying /x=1/, /t=1/ 1.407 +leaves you with two potential possibilities for /X/ =\pm 1.) 1.408 + 1.409 +A function like /f/ has to possess one more propery in order to 1.410 +express a constraint relationship: it must be monotonic in 1.411 +each of its variables /X/, /x/, and /t/. 1.412 +#the partial derivatives of /f/ exist for every allowed combination of 1.413 +#inputs /x/, /X/, and /t/. 1.414 +In other words, the level set has to pass a sort of 1.415 +\ldquo{}vertical line test\rdquo{} for each of its variables.] 1.416 + 1.417 +#Edit Here, Jaynes 1.418 +#is saying that it is possible to express the collection of allowed combinations \(\langle X,x,t \rangle\) of force, quantity, and temperature as a 1.419 +#[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_set][level set]] of some function \(f\). However, not all level sets represent constraint relations; consider \(f(X,x,t)=X^2+x^2+t^2-1\)=0. 1.420 +#In order to specify 1.421 + 1.422 +\begin{equation} 1.423 +f(X,x,t) = O 1.424 +\end{equation} 1.425 + 1.426 +where $X$ is a generalized force (pressure, tension, electric or 1.427 +magnetic field, etc.), $x$ is the corresponding generalized 1.428 +displacement (volume, elongation, electric or magnetic polarization, 1.429 +etc.), and $t$ is the empirical temperature. Equation (1) is 1.430 +called /the equation of state/. 1.431 + 1.432 +At the risk of belaboring it, we emphasize once again that 1.433 +all of this applies only for a system in equilibrium; for 1.434 +otherwise not only.the temperature, but also some or all of the other 1.435 +variables may not be definable. For example, no unique pressure 1.436 +can be assigned to a gas which has just suffered a sudden change 1.437 +in volume, until the generated sound waves have died out. 1.438 + 1.439 +Independently of its functional form, the mere fact of the 1.440 +/existence/ of an equation of state has certain experimental 1.441 +consequences. For example, suppose that in experiments on oxygen 1.442 +gas, in which we control the temperature and pressure 1.443 +independently, we have found that the isothermal compressibility $K$ 1.444 +varies with temperature, and the thermal expansion coefficient 1.445 +\alpha varies with pressure $P$, so that within the accuracy of the data, 1.446 + 1.447 +\begin{equation} 1.448 +\frac{\partial K}{\partial t} = - \frac{\partial \alpha}{\partial P} 1.449 +\end{equation} 1.450 + 1.451 +Is this a particular property of oxygen; or is there reason to 1.452 +believe that it holds also for other substances? Does it depend 1.453 +on our particular choice of a temperature scale? 1.454 + 1.455 +In this case, the answer is found at once; for the definitions of $K$, 1.456 +\alpha are 1.457 + 1.458 +\begin{equation} 1.459 +K = -\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial P},\qquad 1.460 +\alpha=\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial t} 1.461 +\end{equation} 1.462 + 1.463 +which is simply a mathematical expression of the fact that the 1.464 +volume $V$ is a definite function of $P$ and $t$; i.e., it depends 1.465 +only 1.466 +on their present values, and not how those values were attained. 1.467 +In particular, $V$ does not depend on the direction in the \((P, t)\) 1.468 +plane through which the present values were approached; or, as we 1.469 +usually say it, \(dV\) is an /exact differential/. 1.470 + 1.471 +Therefore, although at first glance the relation (2) appears 1.472 +nontrivial and far from obvious, a trivial mathematical analysis 1.473 +convinces us that it must hold regardless of our particular 1.474 +temperature scale, and that it is true not only of oxygen; it must 1.475 +hold for any substance, or mixture of substances, which possesses a 1.476 +definite, reproducible equation of state \(f(P,V,t)=0\). 1.477 + 1.478 +But this understanding also enables us to predict situations in which 1.479 +(2) will /not/ hold. Equation (2), as we have just learned, expresses 1.480 +the fact that an equation of state exists involving only the three 1.481 +variables \((P,V,t)\). Now suppose we try to apply it to a liquid such 1.482 +as nitrobenzene. The nitrobenzene molecule has a large electric dipole 1.483 +moment; and so application of an electric field (as in the 1.484 +[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kerr_effect][electro-optical Kerr cell]]) causes an alignment of molecules which, as 1.485 +accurate measurements will verify, changes the pressure at a given 1.486 +temperature and volume. Therefore, there can no longer exist any 1.487 +unique equation of state involving \((P, V, t)\) only; with 1.488 +sufficiently accurate measurements, nitrobenzene must be regarded as a 1.489 +thermodynamic system with at least three degrees of freedom, and the 1.490 +general equation of state must have at least a complicated a form as 1.491 +\(f(P,V,t,E) = 0\). 1.492 + 1.493 +But if we introduce a varying electric field $E$ into the discussion, 1.494 +the resulting varying electric polarization $M$ also becomes a new 1.495 +thermodynamic variable capable of being measured. Experimentally, it 1.496 +is easiest to control temperature, pressure, and electric field 1.497 +independently, and of course we find that both the volume and 1.498 +polarization are then determined; i.e., there must exist functional 1.499 +relations of the form \(V = V(P,t,E)\), \(M = M(P,t,E)\), or in more 1.500 +symmetrical form 1.501 + 1.502 +\begin{equation} 1.503 +f(V,P,t,E) = 0 \qquad g(M,P,t,E)=0. 1.504 +\end{equation} 1.505 + 1.506 +In other words, if we regard nitrobenzene as a thermodynamic system of 1.507 +three degrees of freedom (i.e., having specified three parameters 1.508 +arbitrarily, all others are then determined), it must possess two 1.509 +independent equations of state. 1.510 + 1.511 +Similarly, a thermodynamic system with four degrees of freedom, 1.512 +defined by the termperature and three pairs of conjugate forces and 1.513 +displacements, will have three independent equations of state, etc. 1.514 + 1.515 +Now, returning to our original question, if nitrobenzene possesses 1.516 +this extra electrical degree of freedom, under what circumstances do 1.517 +we exprect to find a reproducible equation of state involving 1.518 +\((p,V,t)\) only? Evidently, if $E$ is held constant, then the first 1.519 +of equations (1-5) becomes such an equation of state, involving $E$ as 1.520 +a fixed parameter; we would find many different equations of state of 1.521 +the form \(f(P,V,t) = 0\) with a different function $f$ for each 1.522 +different value of the electric field. Likewise, if \(M\) is held 1.523 +constant, we can eliminate \(E\) between equations (1-5) and find a 1.524 +relation \(h(P,V,t,M)=0\), which is an equation of state for 1.525 +\((P,V,t)\) containing \(M\) as a fixed parameter. 1.526 + 1.527 +More generally, if an electrical constraint is imposed on the system 1.528 +(for example, by connecting an external charged capacitor to the 1.529 +electrodes) so that \(M\) is determined by \(E\); i.e., there is a 1.530 +functional relation of the form 1.531 + 1.532 +\begin{equation} 1.533 +g(M,E) = \text{const.} 1.534 +\end{equation} 1.535 + 1.536 +then (1-5) and (1-6) constitute three simultaneous equations, from 1.537 +which both \(E\) and \(M\) may be eliminated mathematically, leading 1.538 +to a relation of the form \(h(P,V,t;q)=0\), which is an equation of 1.539 +state for \((P,V,t)\) involving the fixed parameter \(q\). 1.540 + 1.541 +We see, then, that as long as a fixed constraint of the form (1-6) is 1.542 +imposed on the electrical degree of freedom, we can still observe a 1.543 +reproducible equation of state for nitrobenzene, considered as a 1.544 +thermodynamic system of only two degrees of freedom. If, however, this 1.545 +electrical constraint is removed, so that as we vary $P$ and $t$, the 1.546 +values of $E$ and $M$ vary in an uncontrolled way over a 1.547 +/two-dimensional/ region of the \((E, M)\) plane, then we will find no 1.548 +definite equation of state involving only \((P,V,t)\). 1.549 + 1.550 +This may be stated more colloqually as follows: even though a system 1.551 +has three degrees of freedom, we can still consider only the variables 1.552 +belonging to two of them, and we will find a definite equation of 1.553 +state, /provided/ that in the course of the experiments, the unused 1.554 +degree of freedom is not \ldquo{}tampered with\rdquo{} in an 1.555 +uncontrolled way. 1.556 + 1.557 +We have already emphasized that any physical system corresponds to 1.558 +many different thermodynamic systems, depending on which variables we 1.559 +choose to control and measure. In fact, it is easy to see that any 1.560 +physical system has, for all practical purposes, an /arbitrarily 1.561 +large/ number of degrees of freedom. In the case of nitrobenzene, for 1.562 +example, we may impose any variety of nonuniform electric fields on 1.563 +our sample. Suppose we place $(n+1)$
2.1 Binary file sources/stat.mech.1.pdf has changed
3.1 Binary file sources/stat.mech.2.pdf has changed
4.1 Binary file sources/stat.mech.5.pdf has changed