# HG changeset patch # User Dylan Holmes # Date 1335659570 18000 # Node ID 26acdaf2e8c753921917294f912b0362db09f4ec beginit begins. diff -r 000000000000 -r 26acdaf2e8c7 org/stat-mech.org --- /dev/null Thu Jan 01 00:00:00 1970 +0000 +++ b/org/stat-mech.org Sat Apr 28 19:32:50 2012 -0500 @@ -0,0 +1,560 @@ +#+TITLE: Statistical Mechanics +#+AUTHOR: E.T. Jaynes; edited by Dylan Holmes +#+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu +#+KEYWORDS: statistical mechanics, thermostatics, thermodynamics, temperature, paradoxes, Jaynes +#+SETUPFILE: ../../aurellem/org/setup.org +#+INCLUDE: ../../aurellem/org/level-0.org +#+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"http://www.aurellem.org/MathJax/MathJax.js" + +# "extensions/eqn-number.js" + +#+begin_quote +*Note:* The following is a typeset version of + [[../sources/stat.mech.1.pdf][this unpublished book draft]], written by [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Edwin_Thompson_Jaynes][E.T. Jaynes]]. I have only made + minor changes, e.g. to correct typographical errors, add references, or format equations. The + content itself is intact. --- Dylan +#+end_quote + +* Development of Thermodynamics +Our first intuitive, or \ldquo{}subjective\rdquo{} notions of temperature +arise from the sensations of warmth and cold associated with our +sense of touch . Yet science has been able to convert this qualitative +sensation into an accurately defined quantitative notion, +which can be applied far beyond the range of our direct experience. +Today an experimentalist will report confidently that his +spin system was at a temperature of 2.51 degrees Kelvin; and a +theoretician will report with almost as much confidence that the +temperature at the center of the sun is about \(2 \times 10^7\) degrees +Kelvin. + +The /fact/ that this has proved possible, and the main technical +ideas involved, are assumed already known to the reader; +and we are not concerned here with repeating standard material +already available in a dozen other textbooks . However +thermodynamics, in spite of its great successes, firmly established +for over a century, has also produced a great deal of confusion +and a long list of \ldquo{}paradoxes\rdquo{} centering mostly +around the second law and the nature of irreversibility. +For this reason and others noted below, we want to dwell here at +some length on the /logic/ underlying the development of +thermodynamics . Our aim is to emphasize certain points which, +in the writer's opinion, are essential for clearing up the +confusion and resolving the paradoxes; but which are not +sufficiently ernphasized---and indeed in many cases are +totally ignored---in other textbooks. + +This attention to logic +would not be particularly needed if we regarded classical +thermodynamics (or, as it is becoming called increasingly, +/thermostatics/) as a closed subject, in which the fundamentals +are already completely established, and there is +nothing more to be learned about them. A person who believes +this will probably prefer a pure axiomatic approach, in which +the basic laws are simply stated as arbitrary axioms, without +any attempt to present the evidence for them; and one proceeds +directly to working out their consequences. +However, we take the attitude here that thermostatics, for +all its venerable age, is very far from being a closed subject, +we still have a great deal to learn about such matters as the +most general definitions of equilibrium and reversibility, the +exact range of validity of various statements of the second and +third laws, the necessary and sufficient conditions for +applicability of thermodynamics to special cases such as +spin systems, and how thermodynamics can be applied to such +systems as putty or polyethylene, which deform under force, +but retain a \ldquo{}memory\rdquo{} of their past deformations. +Is it possible to apply thermodynamics to a system such as a vibrating quartz crystal? We can by +no means rule out the possibility that still more laws of +thermodynamics exist, as yet undiscovered, which would be +useful in such applications. + + +It is only by careful examination of the logic by which +present thermodynamics was created, asking exactly how much of +it is mathematical theorems, how much is deducible from the laws +of mechanics and electrodynamics, and how much rests only on +empirical evidence, how compelling is present evidence for the +accuracy and range of validity of its laws; in other words, +exactly where are the boundaries of present knowledge, that we +can hope to uncover new things. Clearly, much research is still +needed in this field, and we shall be able to accomplish only a +small part of this program in the present review. + + +It will develop that there is an astonishingly close analogy +with the logic underlying statistical theory in general, where +again a qualitative feeling that we all have (for the degrees of +plausibility of various unproved and undisproved assertions) must +be convertefi into a precisely defined quantitative concept +(probability). Our later development of probability theory in +Chapter 6,7 will be, to a considerable degree, a paraphrase +of our present review of the logic underlying classical +thermodynamics. + +** The Primitive Thermometer. + +The earliest stages of our +story are necessarily speculative, since they took place long +before the beginnings of recorded history. But we can hardly +doubt that primitive man learned quickly that objects exposed +to the sun‘s rays or placed near a fire felt different from +those in the shade away from fires; and the same difference was +noted between animal bodies and inanimate objects. + + +As soon as it was noted that changes in this feeling of +warmth were correlated with other observable changes in the +behavior of objects, such as the boiling and freezing of water, +cooking of meat, melting of fat and wax, etc., the notion of +warmth took its first step away from the purely subjective +toward an objective, physical notion capable of being studied +scientifically. + +One of the most striking manifestations of warmth (but far +from the earliest discovered) is the almost universal expansion +of gases, liquids, and solids when heated . This property has +proved to be a convenient one with which to reduce the notion +of warmth to something entirely objective. The invention of the +/thermometer/, in which expansion of a mercury column, or a gas, +or the bending of a bimetallic strip, etc. is read off on a +suitable scale, thereby giving us a /number/ with which to work, +was a necessary prelude to even the crudest study of the physical +nature of heat. To the best of our knowledge, although the +necessary technology to do this had been available for at least +3,000 years, the first person to carry it out in practice was +Galileo, in 1592. + +Later on we will give more precise definitions of the term +\ldquo{}thermometer.\rdquo{} But at the present stage we +are not in a position to do so (as Galileo was not), because +the very concepts needed have not yet been developed; +more precise definitions can be +given only after our study has revealed the need for them. In +deed, our final definition can be given only after the full +mathematical formalism of statistical mechanics is at hand. + +Once a thermometer has been constructed, and the scale +marked off in a quite arbitrary way (although we will suppose +that the scale is at least monotonic: i.e., greater warmth always +corresponds to a greater number), we are ready to begin scien +tific experiments in thermodynamics. The number read eff from +any such instrument is called the /empirical temperature/, and we +denote it by \(t\). Since the exact calibration of the thermometer +is not specified), any monotonic increasing function +\(t‘ = f(t)\) provides an equally good temperature scale for the +present. + + +** Thermodynamic Systems. + +The \ldquo{}thermodynamic systems\rdquo{} which +are the objects of our study may be, physically, almost any +collections of objects. The traditional simplest system with +which to begin a study of thermodynamics is a volume of gas. +We shall, however, be concerned from the start also with such +things as a stretched wire or membrane, an electric cell, a +polarized dielectric, a paramagnetic body in a magnetic field, etc. + +The /thermodynamic state/ of such a system is determined by +specifying (i.e., measuring) certain macrcoscopic physical +properties. Now, any real physical system has many millions of such +preperties; in order to have a usable theory we cannot require +that /all/ of them be specified. We see, therefore, that there +must be a clear distinction between the notions of +\ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} and \ldquo{}physical +system.\rdquo{} +A given /physical/ system may correspond to many different +/thermodynamic systems/, depending +on which variables we choose to measure or control; and which +we decide to leave unmeasured and/or uncontrolled. + + +For example, our physical system might consist of a crystal +of sodium chloride. For one set of experiments we work with +temperature, volume, and pressure; and ignore its electrical +properties. For another set of experiments we work with +temperature, electric field, and electric polarization; and +ignore the varying stress and strain. The /physical/ system, +therefore, corresponds to two entirely different /thermodynamic/ +systems. Exactly how much freedom, then, do we have in choosing +the variables which shall define the thermodynamic state of our +system? How many must we choose? What [criteria] determine when +we have made an adequate choice? These questions cannot be +answered until we say a little more about what we are trying to +accomplish by a thermodynamic theory. A mere collection of +recorded data about our system, as in the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CRC_Handbook_of_Chemistry_and_Physics][/Handbook of Physics and +Chemistry/]], is a very useful thing, but it hardly constitutes +a theory. In order to construct anything deserving of such a +name, the primary requirement is that we can recognize some kind +of reproducible connection between the different properties con +sidered, so that information about some of them will enable us +to predict others. And of course, in order that our theory can +be called thermodynamics (and not some other area of physics), +it is necessary that the temperature be one of the quantities +involved in a nontrivial way. + +The gist of these remarks is that the notion of +\ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} is in part +an anthropomorphic one; it is for us to +say which set of variables shall be used. If two different +choices both lead to useful reproducible connections, it is quite +meaningless to say that one choice is any more \ldquo{}correct\rdquo{} +than the other. Recognition of this fact will prove crucial later in +avoiding certain ancient paradoxes. + +At this stage we can determine only empirically which other +physical properties need to be introduced before reproducible +connections appear. Once any such connection is established, we +can analyze it with the hope of being able to (1) reduce it to a +/logical/ connection rather than an empirical one; and (2) extend +it to an hypothesis applying beyond the original data, which +enables us to predict further connections capable of being +tested by experiment. Examples of this will be given presently. + + +There will remain, however, a few reproducible relations +which to the best of present knowledge, are not reducible to +logical relations within the context of classical thermodynamics +(and. whose demonstration in the wider context of mechanics, +electrodynamics, and quantum theory remains one of probability +rather than logical proof); from the standpoint of thermodynamics +these remain simply statements of empirical fact which must be +accepted as such without any deeper basis, but without which the +development of thermodynamics cannot proceed. Because of this +special status, these relations have become known as the +\ldquo{}laws\rdquo{} +of thermodynamics . The most fundamental one is a qualitative +rather than quantitative relation, the \ldquo{}zero'th law.\rdquo{} + +** Equilibrium; the \ldquo{}Zero‘th Law.\rdquo{} + + It is a common experience +that when objects are placed in contact with each other but +isolated from their surroundings, they may undergo observable +changes for a time as a result; one body may become warmer, +another cooler, the pressure of a gas or volume of a liquid may +change; stress or magnetization in a solid may change, etc. But +after a sufficient time, the observable macroscopic properties +settle down to a steady condition, after which no further changes +are seen unless there is a new intervention from the outside. +When this steady condition is reached, the experimentalist says +that the objects have reached a state of /equilibrium/ with each +other. Once again, more precise definitions of this term will +be needed eventually, but they require concepts not yet developed. +In any event, the criterion just stated is almost the only one +used in actual laboratory practice to decide when equilibrium +has been reached. + + +A particular case of equilibrium is encountered when we +place a thermometer in contact with another body. The reading +\(t\) of the thermometer may vary at first, but eventually it reach es +a steady value. Now the number \(t\) read by a thermometer is always. +by definition, the empirical temperature /of the thermometer/ (more +precisely, of the sensitive element of the thermometer). When +this number is constant in time, we say that the thermometer is +in /thermal equilibrium/ with its surroundings; and we then extend +the notion of temperature, calling the steady value \(t\) also the +/temperature of the surroundings/. + +We have repeated these elementary facts, well known to every +child, in order to emphasize this point: Thermodynamics can be +a theory /only/ of states of equilibrium, because the very +procedure by which the temperature of a system is defined by +operational means, already presupposes the attainment of +equilibrium. Strictly speaking, therefore, classical +thermodynamics does not even contain the concept of a +\ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} + +Of course, to recognize this limitation on conventional +thermodynamics (best emphasized by calling it instead, +thermostatics) in no way rules out the possibility of +generalizing the notion of temperature to nonequilibrium states. +Indeed, it is clear that one could define any number of +time-dependent quantities all of which reduce, in the special +case of equilibrium, to the temperature as defined above. +Historically, attempts to do this even antedated the discovery +of the laws of thermodynamics, as is demonstrated by +\ldquo{}Newton's law of cooling.\rdquo{} Therefore, the +question is not whether generalization is /possible/, but only +whether it is in any way /useful/; i.e., does the temperature so +generalized have any connection with other physical properties +of our system, so that it could help us to predict other things? +However, to raise such questions takes us far beyond the +domain of thermostatics; and the general laws of nonequilibrium +behavior are so much more complicated that it would be virtually +hopeless to try to unravel them by empirical means alone. For +example, even if two different kinds of thermometer are calibrated +so that they agree with each other in equilibrium situations, +they will not agree in general about the momentary value a +\ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} To make any real +progress in this area, we have to supplement empirical observation by the guidance +of a rather hiqhly-developed theory. The notion of a +time-dependent temperature is far from simple conceptually, and we +will find that nothing very helpful can be said about this until +the full mathematical apparatus of nonequilibrium statistical +mechanics has been developed. + +Suppose now that two bodies have the same temperature; i.e., +a given thermometer reads the same steady value when in contact +with either. In order that the statement, \ldquo{}two bodies have the +same temperature\rdquo{} shall describe a physi cal property of the bodies, +and not merely an accidental circumstance due to our having used +a particular kind of thermometer, it is necessary that /all/ +thermometers agree in assigning equal temperatures to them if +/any/ thermometer does . Only experiment is competent to determine +whether this universality property is true. Unfortunately, the +writer must confess that he is unable to cite any definite +experiment in which this point was subjected to a careful test. +That equality of temperatures has this absolute meaning, has +evidently been taken for granted so much that (like absolute +sirnultaneity in pre-relativity physics) most of us are not even +consciously aware that we make such an assumption in +thermodynamics. However, for the present we can only take it as a familiar +empirical fact that this condition does hold, not because we can +cite positive evidence for it, but because of the absence of +negative evidence against it; i.e., we think that, if an +exception had ever been found, this would have created a sensation in +physics, and we should have heard of it. + +We now ask: when two bodies are at the same temperature, +are they then in thermal equilibrium with each other? Again, +only experiment is competent to answer this; the general +conclusion, again supported more by absence of negative evidence +than by specific positive evidence, is that the relation of +equilibrium has this property: +#+begin_quote +/Two bodies in thermal equilibrium +with a third body, are thermal equilibrium with each other./ +#+end_quote + +This empirical fact is usually called the \ldquo{}zero'th law of +thermodynamics.\rdquo{} Since nothing prevents us from regarding a +thermometer as the \ldquo{}third body\rdquo{} in the above statement, +it appears that we may also state the zero'th law as: +#+begin_quote +/Two bodies are in thermal equilibrium with each other when they are +at the same temperature./ +#+end_quote +Although from the preceding discussion it might appear that +these two statements of the zero'th law are entirely equivalent +(and we certainly have no empirical evidence against either), it +is interesting to note that there are theoretical reasons, arising +from General Relativity, indicating that while the first +statement may be universally valid, the second is not. When we +consider equilibrium in a gravitational field, the verification +that two bodies have equal temperatures may require transport +of the thermometer through a gravitational potential difference; +and this introduces a new element into the discussion. We will +consider this in more detail in a later Chapter, and show that +according to General Relativity, equilibrium in a large system +requires, not that the temperature be uniform at all points, but +rather that a particular function of temperature and gravitational +potential be constant (the function is \(T\cdot \exp{(\Phi/c^2})\), where +\(T\) is the Kelvin temperature to be defined later, and \(\Phi\) is the +gravitational potential). + +Of course, this effect is so small that ordinary terrestrial +experiments would need to have a precision many orders of +magnitude beyond that presently possible, before one could hope even +to detect it; and needless to say, it has played no role in the +development of thermodynamics. For present purposes, therefore, +we need not distinguish between the two above statements of the +zero'th law, and we take it as a basic empirical fact that a +uniform temperature at all points of a system is an essential +condition for equilibrium. It is an important part of our +ivestigation to determine whether there are other essential +conditions as well. In fact, as we will find, there are many +different kinds of equilibrium; and failure to distinguish between +them can be a prolific source of paradoxes. + +** Equation of State +Another important reproducible connection is found when +we consider a thermodynamic system defined by +three parameters; in addition to the temperature we choose a +\ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{} and a conjugate \ldquo{}force.\rdquo{} +Subject to some qualifications given below, we find experimentally +that these parameters are not independent, but are subject to a constraint. +For example, we cannot vary the equilibrium pressure, volume, +and temperature of a given mass of gas independently; it is found +that a given pressure and volume can be realized only at one +particular temperature, that the gas will assume a given tempera~ +ture and volume only at one particular pressure, etc. Similarly, +a stretched wire can be made to have arbitrarily assigned tension +and elongation only if its temperature is suitably chosen, a +dielectric will assume a state of given temperature and +polarization at only one value of the electric field, etc. +These simplest nontrivial thermodynamic systems (three +parameters with one constraint) are said to possess two +/degrees of freedom/; for the range of possible equilibrium states is defined +by specifying any two of the variables arbitrarily, whereupon the +third, and all others we may introduce, are determined. +Mathematically, this is expressed by the existence of a functional +relationship of the form[fn::Edit: The set of solutions to an equation +like /f(X,x,t)=/ const. is called a /level set/. Here, Jaynes is +saying that the quantities /X/, /x/, and /t/ follow a \ldquo{}functional +rule\rdquo{}, so the set of physically allowed combinations of /X/, +/x/, and /t/ in equilibrium states can be +expressed as the level set of a function. + +But not every function expresses a constraint relation; for some +functions, you can specify two of the variables, and the third will +still be undetermined. (For example, if f=X^2+x^2+t^2-3, +the level set /f(X,x,t)=0/ is a sphere, and specifying /x=1/, /t=1/ +leaves you with two potential possibilities for /X/ =\pm 1.) + +A function like /f/ has to possess one more propery in order to +express a constraint relationship: it must be monotonic in +each of its variables /X/, /x/, and /t/. +#the partial derivatives of /f/ exist for every allowed combination of +#inputs /x/, /X/, and /t/. +In other words, the level set has to pass a sort of +\ldquo{}vertical line test\rdquo{} for each of its variables.] + +#Edit Here, Jaynes +#is saying that it is possible to express the collection of allowed combinations \(\langle X,x,t \rangle\) of force, quantity, and temperature as a +#[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_set][level set]] of some function \(f\). However, not all level sets represent constraint relations; consider \(f(X,x,t)=X^2+x^2+t^2-1\)=0. +#In order to specify + +\begin{equation} +f(X,x,t) = O +\end{equation} + +where $X$ is a generalized force (pressure, tension, electric or +magnetic field, etc.), $x$ is the corresponding generalized +displacement (volume, elongation, electric or magnetic polarization, +etc.), and $t$ is the empirical temperature. Equation (1) is +called /the equation of state/. + +At the risk of belaboring it, we emphasize once again that +all of this applies only for a system in equilibrium; for +otherwise not only.the temperature, but also some or all of the other +variables may not be definable. For example, no unique pressure +can be assigned to a gas which has just suffered a sudden change +in volume, until the generated sound waves have died out. + +Independently of its functional form, the mere fact of the +/existence/ of an equation of state has certain experimental +consequences. For example, suppose that in experiments on oxygen +gas, in which we control the temperature and pressure +independently, we have found that the isothermal compressibility $K$ +varies with temperature, and the thermal expansion coefficient +\alpha varies with pressure $P$, so that within the accuracy of the data, + +\begin{equation} +\frac{\partial K}{\partial t} = - \frac{\partial \alpha}{\partial P} +\end{equation} + +Is this a particular property of oxygen; or is there reason to +believe that it holds also for other substances? Does it depend +on our particular choice of a temperature scale? + +In this case, the answer is found at once; for the definitions of $K$, +\alpha are + +\begin{equation} +K = -\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial P},\qquad +\alpha=\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial t} +\end{equation} + +which is simply a mathematical expression of the fact that the +volume $V$ is a definite function of $P$ and $t$; i.e., it depends +only +on their present values, and not how those values were attained. +In particular, $V$ does not depend on the direction in the \((P, t)\) +plane through which the present values were approached; or, as we +usually say it, \(dV\) is an /exact differential/. + +Therefore, although at first glance the relation (2) appears +nontrivial and far from obvious, a trivial mathematical analysis +convinces us that it must hold regardless of our particular +temperature scale, and that it is true not only of oxygen; it must +hold for any substance, or mixture of substances, which possesses a +definite, reproducible equation of state \(f(P,V,t)=0\). + +But this understanding also enables us to predict situations in which +(2) will /not/ hold. Equation (2), as we have just learned, expresses +the fact that an equation of state exists involving only the three +variables \((P,V,t)\). Now suppose we try to apply it to a liquid such +as nitrobenzene. The nitrobenzene molecule has a large electric dipole +moment; and so application of an electric field (as in the +[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kerr_effect][electro-optical Kerr cell]]) causes an alignment of molecules which, as +accurate measurements will verify, changes the pressure at a given +temperature and volume. Therefore, there can no longer exist any +unique equation of state involving \((P, V, t)\) only; with +sufficiently accurate measurements, nitrobenzene must be regarded as a +thermodynamic system with at least three degrees of freedom, and the +general equation of state must have at least a complicated a form as +\(f(P,V,t,E) = 0\). + +But if we introduce a varying electric field $E$ into the discussion, +the resulting varying electric polarization $M$ also becomes a new +thermodynamic variable capable of being measured. Experimentally, it +is easiest to control temperature, pressure, and electric field +independently, and of course we find that both the volume and +polarization are then determined; i.e., there must exist functional +relations of the form \(V = V(P,t,E)\), \(M = M(P,t,E)\), or in more +symmetrical form + +\begin{equation} +f(V,P,t,E) = 0 \qquad g(M,P,t,E)=0. +\end{equation} + +In other words, if we regard nitrobenzene as a thermodynamic system of +three degrees of freedom (i.e., having specified three parameters +arbitrarily, all others are then determined), it must possess two +independent equations of state. + +Similarly, a thermodynamic system with four degrees of freedom, +defined by the termperature and three pairs of conjugate forces and +displacements, will have three independent equations of state, etc. + +Now, returning to our original question, if nitrobenzene possesses +this extra electrical degree of freedom, under what circumstances do +we exprect to find a reproducible equation of state involving +\((p,V,t)\) only? Evidently, if $E$ is held constant, then the first +of equations (1-5) becomes such an equation of state, involving $E$ as +a fixed parameter; we would find many different equations of state of +the form \(f(P,V,t) = 0\) with a different function $f$ for each +different value of the electric field. Likewise, if \(M\) is held +constant, we can eliminate \(E\) between equations (1-5) and find a +relation \(h(P,V,t,M)=0\), which is an equation of state for +\((P,V,t)\) containing \(M\) as a fixed parameter. + +More generally, if an electrical constraint is imposed on the system +(for example, by connecting an external charged capacitor to the +electrodes) so that \(M\) is determined by \(E\); i.e., there is a +functional relation of the form + +\begin{equation} +g(M,E) = \text{const.} +\end{equation} + +then (1-5) and (1-6) constitute three simultaneous equations, from +which both \(E\) and \(M\) may be eliminated mathematically, leading +to a relation of the form \(h(P,V,t;q)=0\), which is an equation of +state for \((P,V,t)\) involving the fixed parameter \(q\). + +We see, then, that as long as a fixed constraint of the form (1-6) is +imposed on the electrical degree of freedom, we can still observe a +reproducible equation of state for nitrobenzene, considered as a +thermodynamic system of only two degrees of freedom. If, however, this +electrical constraint is removed, so that as we vary $P$ and $t$, the +values of $E$ and $M$ vary in an uncontrolled way over a +/two-dimensional/ region of the \((E, M)\) plane, then we will find no +definite equation of state involving only \((P,V,t)\). + +This may be stated more colloqually as follows: even though a system +has three degrees of freedom, we can still consider only the variables +belonging to two of them, and we will find a definite equation of +state, /provided/ that in the course of the experiments, the unused +degree of freedom is not \ldquo{}tampered with\rdquo{} in an +uncontrolled way. + +We have already emphasized that any physical system corresponds to +many different thermodynamic systems, depending on which variables we +choose to control and measure. In fact, it is easy to see that any +physical system has, for all practical purposes, an /arbitrarily +large/ number of degrees of freedom. In the case of nitrobenzene, for +example, we may impose any variety of nonuniform electric fields on +our sample. Suppose we place $(n+1)$ diff -r 000000000000 -r 26acdaf2e8c7 sources/stat.mech.1.pdf Binary file sources/stat.mech.1.pdf has changed diff -r 000000000000 -r 26acdaf2e8c7 sources/stat.mech.2.pdf Binary file sources/stat.mech.2.pdf has changed diff -r 000000000000 -r 26acdaf2e8c7 sources/stat.mech.5.pdf Binary file sources/stat.mech.5.pdf has changed