ocsenave@0: #+TITLE: Statistical Mechanics ocsenave@0: #+AUTHOR: E.T. Jaynes; edited by Dylan Holmes ocsenave@0: #+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu ocsenave@0: #+KEYWORDS: statistical mechanics, thermostatics, thermodynamics, temperature, paradoxes, Jaynes ocsenave@0: #+SETUPFILE: ../../aurellem/org/setup.org ocsenave@0: #+INCLUDE: ../../aurellem/org/level-0.org ocsenave@0: #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"http://www.aurellem.org/MathJax/MathJax.js" ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: # "extensions/eqn-number.js" ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: #+begin_quote ocsenave@0: *Note:* The following is a typeset version of ocsenave@0: [[../sources/stat.mech.1.pdf][this unpublished book draft]], written by [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Edwin_Thompson_Jaynes][E.T. Jaynes]]. I have only made ocsenave@0: minor changes, e.g. to correct typographical errors, add references, or format equations. The ocsenave@0: content itself is intact. --- Dylan ocsenave@0: #+end_quote ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: * Development of Thermodynamics ocsenave@0: Our first intuitive, or \ldquo{}subjective\rdquo{} notions of temperature ocsenave@0: arise from the sensations of warmth and cold associated with our ocsenave@0: sense of touch . Yet science has been able to convert this qualitative ocsenave@0: sensation into an accurately defined quantitative notion, ocsenave@0: which can be applied far beyond the range of our direct experience. ocsenave@0: Today an experimentalist will report confidently that his ocsenave@0: spin system was at a temperature of 2.51 degrees Kelvin; and a ocsenave@0: theoretician will report with almost as much confidence that the ocsenave@0: temperature at the center of the sun is about \(2 \times 10^7\) degrees ocsenave@0: Kelvin. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: The /fact/ that this has proved possible, and the main technical ocsenave@0: ideas involved, are assumed already known to the reader; ocsenave@0: and we are not concerned here with repeating standard material ocsenave@0: already available in a dozen other textbooks . However ocsenave@0: thermodynamics, in spite of its great successes, firmly established ocsenave@0: for over a century, has also produced a great deal of confusion ocsenave@0: and a long list of \ldquo{}paradoxes\rdquo{} centering mostly ocsenave@0: around the second law and the nature of irreversibility. ocsenave@0: For this reason and others noted below, we want to dwell here at ocsenave@0: some length on the /logic/ underlying the development of ocsenave@0: thermodynamics . Our aim is to emphasize certain points which, ocsenave@0: in the writer's opinion, are essential for clearing up the ocsenave@0: confusion and resolving the paradoxes; but which are not ocsenave@0: sufficiently ernphasized---and indeed in many cases are ocsenave@0: totally ignored---in other textbooks. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: This attention to logic ocsenave@0: would not be particularly needed if we regarded classical ocsenave@0: thermodynamics (or, as it is becoming called increasingly, ocsenave@0: /thermostatics/) as a closed subject, in which the fundamentals ocsenave@0: are already completely established, and there is ocsenave@0: nothing more to be learned about them. A person who believes ocsenave@0: this will probably prefer a pure axiomatic approach, in which ocsenave@0: the basic laws are simply stated as arbitrary axioms, without ocsenave@0: any attempt to present the evidence for them; and one proceeds ocsenave@0: directly to working out their consequences. ocsenave@0: However, we take the attitude here that thermostatics, for ocsenave@0: all its venerable age, is very far from being a closed subject, ocsenave@0: we still have a great deal to learn about such matters as the ocsenave@0: most general definitions of equilibrium and reversibility, the ocsenave@0: exact range of validity of various statements of the second and ocsenave@0: third laws, the necessary and sufficient conditions for ocsenave@0: applicability of thermodynamics to special cases such as ocsenave@0: spin systems, and how thermodynamics can be applied to such ocsenave@0: systems as putty or polyethylene, which deform under force, ocsenave@0: but retain a \ldquo{}memory\rdquo{} of their past deformations. ocsenave@0: Is it possible to apply thermodynamics to a system such as a vibrating quartz crystal? We can by ocsenave@0: no means rule out the possibility that still more laws of ocsenave@0: thermodynamics exist, as yet undiscovered, which would be ocsenave@0: useful in such applications. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: It is only by careful examination of the logic by which ocsenave@0: present thermodynamics was created, asking exactly how much of ocsenave@0: it is mathematical theorems, how much is deducible from the laws ocsenave@0: of mechanics and electrodynamics, and how much rests only on ocsenave@0: empirical evidence, how compelling is present evidence for the ocsenave@0: accuracy and range of validity of its laws; in other words, ocsenave@0: exactly where are the boundaries of present knowledge, that we ocsenave@0: can hope to uncover new things. Clearly, much research is still ocsenave@0: needed in this field, and we shall be able to accomplish only a ocsenave@0: small part of this program in the present review. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: It will develop that there is an astonishingly close analogy ocsenave@0: with the logic underlying statistical theory in general, where ocsenave@0: again a qualitative feeling that we all have (for the degrees of ocsenave@0: plausibility of various unproved and undisproved assertions) must ocsenave@0: be convertefi into a precisely defined quantitative concept ocsenave@0: (probability). Our later development of probability theory in ocsenave@0: Chapter 6,7 will be, to a considerable degree, a paraphrase ocsenave@0: of our present review of the logic underlying classical ocsenave@0: thermodynamics. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ** The Primitive Thermometer. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: The earliest stages of our ocsenave@0: story are necessarily speculative, since they took place long ocsenave@0: before the beginnings of recorded history. But we can hardly ocsenave@0: doubt that primitive man learned quickly that objects exposed ocsenave@0: to the sun‘s rays or placed near a fire felt different from ocsenave@0: those in the shade away from fires; and the same difference was ocsenave@0: noted between animal bodies and inanimate objects. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: As soon as it was noted that changes in this feeling of ocsenave@0: warmth were correlated with other observable changes in the ocsenave@0: behavior of objects, such as the boiling and freezing of water, ocsenave@0: cooking of meat, melting of fat and wax, etc., the notion of ocsenave@0: warmth took its first step away from the purely subjective ocsenave@0: toward an objective, physical notion capable of being studied ocsenave@0: scientifically. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: One of the most striking manifestations of warmth (but far ocsenave@0: from the earliest discovered) is the almost universal expansion ocsenave@0: of gases, liquids, and solids when heated . This property has ocsenave@0: proved to be a convenient one with which to reduce the notion ocsenave@0: of warmth to something entirely objective. The invention of the ocsenave@0: /thermometer/, in which expansion of a mercury column, or a gas, ocsenave@0: or the bending of a bimetallic strip, etc. is read off on a ocsenave@0: suitable scale, thereby giving us a /number/ with which to work, ocsenave@0: was a necessary prelude to even the crudest study of the physical ocsenave@0: nature of heat. To the best of our knowledge, although the ocsenave@0: necessary technology to do this had been available for at least ocsenave@0: 3,000 years, the first person to carry it out in practice was ocsenave@0: Galileo, in 1592. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Later on we will give more precise definitions of the term ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}thermometer.\rdquo{} But at the present stage we ocsenave@0: are not in a position to do so (as Galileo was not), because ocsenave@0: the very concepts needed have not yet been developed; ocsenave@0: more precise definitions can be ocsenave@0: given only after our study has revealed the need for them. In ocsenave@0: deed, our final definition can be given only after the full ocsenave@0: mathematical formalism of statistical mechanics is at hand. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Once a thermometer has been constructed, and the scale ocsenave@0: marked off in a quite arbitrary way (although we will suppose ocsenave@0: that the scale is at least monotonic: i.e., greater warmth always ocsenave@0: corresponds to a greater number), we are ready to begin scien ocsenave@0: tific experiments in thermodynamics. The number read eff from ocsenave@0: any such instrument is called the /empirical temperature/, and we ocsenave@0: denote it by \(t\). Since the exact calibration of the thermometer ocsenave@0: is not specified), any monotonic increasing function ocsenave@0: \(t‘ = f(t)\) provides an equally good temperature scale for the ocsenave@0: present. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ** Thermodynamic Systems. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: The \ldquo{}thermodynamic systems\rdquo{} which ocsenave@0: are the objects of our study may be, physically, almost any ocsenave@0: collections of objects. The traditional simplest system with ocsenave@0: which to begin a study of thermodynamics is a volume of gas. ocsenave@0: We shall, however, be concerned from the start also with such ocsenave@0: things as a stretched wire or membrane, an electric cell, a ocsenave@0: polarized dielectric, a paramagnetic body in a magnetic field, etc. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: The /thermodynamic state/ of such a system is determined by ocsenave@0: specifying (i.e., measuring) certain macrcoscopic physical ocsenave@0: properties. Now, any real physical system has many millions of such ocsenave@0: preperties; in order to have a usable theory we cannot require ocsenave@0: that /all/ of them be specified. We see, therefore, that there ocsenave@0: must be a clear distinction between the notions of ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} and \ldquo{}physical ocsenave@0: system.\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: A given /physical/ system may correspond to many different ocsenave@0: /thermodynamic systems/, depending ocsenave@0: on which variables we choose to measure or control; and which ocsenave@0: we decide to leave unmeasured and/or uncontrolled. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: For example, our physical system might consist of a crystal ocsenave@0: of sodium chloride. For one set of experiments we work with ocsenave@0: temperature, volume, and pressure; and ignore its electrical ocsenave@0: properties. For another set of experiments we work with ocsenave@0: temperature, electric field, and electric polarization; and ocsenave@0: ignore the varying stress and strain. The /physical/ system, ocsenave@0: therefore, corresponds to two entirely different /thermodynamic/ ocsenave@0: systems. Exactly how much freedom, then, do we have in choosing ocsenave@0: the variables which shall define the thermodynamic state of our ocsenave@0: system? How many must we choose? What [criteria] determine when ocsenave@0: we have made an adequate choice? These questions cannot be ocsenave@0: answered until we say a little more about what we are trying to ocsenave@0: accomplish by a thermodynamic theory. A mere collection of ocsenave@0: recorded data about our system, as in the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CRC_Handbook_of_Chemistry_and_Physics][/Handbook of Physics and ocsenave@0: Chemistry/]], is a very useful thing, but it hardly constitutes ocsenave@0: a theory. In order to construct anything deserving of such a ocsenave@0: name, the primary requirement is that we can recognize some kind ocsenave@0: of reproducible connection between the different properties con ocsenave@0: sidered, so that information about some of them will enable us ocsenave@0: to predict others. And of course, in order that our theory can ocsenave@0: be called thermodynamics (and not some other area of physics), ocsenave@0: it is necessary that the temperature be one of the quantities ocsenave@0: involved in a nontrivial way. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: The gist of these remarks is that the notion of ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} is in part ocsenave@0: an anthropomorphic one; it is for us to ocsenave@0: say which set of variables shall be used. If two different ocsenave@0: choices both lead to useful reproducible connections, it is quite ocsenave@0: meaningless to say that one choice is any more \ldquo{}correct\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: than the other. Recognition of this fact will prove crucial later in ocsenave@0: avoiding certain ancient paradoxes. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: At this stage we can determine only empirically which other ocsenave@0: physical properties need to be introduced before reproducible ocsenave@0: connections appear. Once any such connection is established, we ocsenave@0: can analyze it with the hope of being able to (1) reduce it to a ocsenave@0: /logical/ connection rather than an empirical one; and (2) extend ocsenave@0: it to an hypothesis applying beyond the original data, which ocsenave@0: enables us to predict further connections capable of being ocsenave@0: tested by experiment. Examples of this will be given presently. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: There will remain, however, a few reproducible relations ocsenave@0: which to the best of present knowledge, are not reducible to ocsenave@0: logical relations within the context of classical thermodynamics ocsenave@0: (and. whose demonstration in the wider context of mechanics, ocsenave@0: electrodynamics, and quantum theory remains one of probability ocsenave@0: rather than logical proof); from the standpoint of thermodynamics ocsenave@0: these remain simply statements of empirical fact which must be ocsenave@0: accepted as such without any deeper basis, but without which the ocsenave@0: development of thermodynamics cannot proceed. Because of this ocsenave@0: special status, these relations have become known as the ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}laws\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: of thermodynamics . The most fundamental one is a qualitative ocsenave@0: rather than quantitative relation, the \ldquo{}zero'th law.\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ** Equilibrium; the \ldquo{}Zero‘th Law.\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: It is a common experience ocsenave@0: that when objects are placed in contact with each other but ocsenave@0: isolated from their surroundings, they may undergo observable ocsenave@0: changes for a time as a result; one body may become warmer, ocsenave@0: another cooler, the pressure of a gas or volume of a liquid may ocsenave@0: change; stress or magnetization in a solid may change, etc. But ocsenave@0: after a sufficient time, the observable macroscopic properties ocsenave@0: settle down to a steady condition, after which no further changes ocsenave@0: are seen unless there is a new intervention from the outside. ocsenave@0: When this steady condition is reached, the experimentalist says ocsenave@0: that the objects have reached a state of /equilibrium/ with each ocsenave@0: other. Once again, more precise definitions of this term will ocsenave@0: be needed eventually, but they require concepts not yet developed. ocsenave@0: In any event, the criterion just stated is almost the only one ocsenave@0: used in actual laboratory practice to decide when equilibrium ocsenave@0: has been reached. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: A particular case of equilibrium is encountered when we ocsenave@0: place a thermometer in contact with another body. The reading ocsenave@0: \(t\) of the thermometer may vary at first, but eventually it reach es ocsenave@0: a steady value. Now the number \(t\) read by a thermometer is always. ocsenave@0: by definition, the empirical temperature /of the thermometer/ (more ocsenave@0: precisely, of the sensitive element of the thermometer). When ocsenave@0: this number is constant in time, we say that the thermometer is ocsenave@0: in /thermal equilibrium/ with its surroundings; and we then extend ocsenave@0: the notion of temperature, calling the steady value \(t\) also the ocsenave@0: /temperature of the surroundings/. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: We have repeated these elementary facts, well known to every ocsenave@0: child, in order to emphasize this point: Thermodynamics can be ocsenave@0: a theory /only/ of states of equilibrium, because the very ocsenave@0: procedure by which the temperature of a system is defined by ocsenave@0: operational means, already presupposes the attainment of ocsenave@0: equilibrium. Strictly speaking, therefore, classical ocsenave@0: thermodynamics does not even contain the concept of a ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Of course, to recognize this limitation on conventional ocsenave@0: thermodynamics (best emphasized by calling it instead, ocsenave@0: thermostatics) in no way rules out the possibility of ocsenave@0: generalizing the notion of temperature to nonequilibrium states. ocsenave@0: Indeed, it is clear that one could define any number of ocsenave@0: time-dependent quantities all of which reduce, in the special ocsenave@0: case of equilibrium, to the temperature as defined above. ocsenave@0: Historically, attempts to do this even antedated the discovery ocsenave@0: of the laws of thermodynamics, as is demonstrated by ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}Newton's law of cooling.\rdquo{} Therefore, the ocsenave@0: question is not whether generalization is /possible/, but only ocsenave@0: whether it is in any way /useful/; i.e., does the temperature so ocsenave@0: generalized have any connection with other physical properties ocsenave@0: of our system, so that it could help us to predict other things? ocsenave@0: However, to raise such questions takes us far beyond the ocsenave@0: domain of thermostatics; and the general laws of nonequilibrium ocsenave@0: behavior are so much more complicated that it would be virtually ocsenave@0: hopeless to try to unravel them by empirical means alone. For ocsenave@0: example, even if two different kinds of thermometer are calibrated ocsenave@0: so that they agree with each other in equilibrium situations, ocsenave@0: they will not agree in general about the momentary value a ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} To make any real ocsenave@0: progress in this area, we have to supplement empirical observation by the guidance ocsenave@0: of a rather hiqhly-developed theory. The notion of a ocsenave@0: time-dependent temperature is far from simple conceptually, and we ocsenave@0: will find that nothing very helpful can be said about this until ocsenave@0: the full mathematical apparatus of nonequilibrium statistical ocsenave@0: mechanics has been developed. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Suppose now that two bodies have the same temperature; i.e., ocsenave@0: a given thermometer reads the same steady value when in contact ocsenave@0: with either. In order that the statement, \ldquo{}two bodies have the ocsenave@0: same temperature\rdquo{} shall describe a physi cal property of the bodies, ocsenave@0: and not merely an accidental circumstance due to our having used ocsenave@0: a particular kind of thermometer, it is necessary that /all/ ocsenave@0: thermometers agree in assigning equal temperatures to them if ocsenave@0: /any/ thermometer does . Only experiment is competent to determine ocsenave@0: whether this universality property is true. Unfortunately, the ocsenave@0: writer must confess that he is unable to cite any definite ocsenave@0: experiment in which this point was subjected to a careful test. ocsenave@0: That equality of temperatures has this absolute meaning, has ocsenave@0: evidently been taken for granted so much that (like absolute ocsenave@0: sirnultaneity in pre-relativity physics) most of us are not even ocsenave@0: consciously aware that we make such an assumption in ocsenave@0: thermodynamics. However, for the present we can only take it as a familiar ocsenave@0: empirical fact that this condition does hold, not because we can ocsenave@0: cite positive evidence for it, but because of the absence of ocsenave@0: negative evidence against it; i.e., we think that, if an ocsenave@0: exception had ever been found, this would have created a sensation in ocsenave@0: physics, and we should have heard of it. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: We now ask: when two bodies are at the same temperature, ocsenave@0: are they then in thermal equilibrium with each other? Again, ocsenave@0: only experiment is competent to answer this; the general ocsenave@0: conclusion, again supported more by absence of negative evidence ocsenave@0: than by specific positive evidence, is that the relation of ocsenave@0: equilibrium has this property: ocsenave@0: #+begin_quote ocsenave@0: /Two bodies in thermal equilibrium ocsenave@0: with a third body, are thermal equilibrium with each other./ ocsenave@0: #+end_quote ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: This empirical fact is usually called the \ldquo{}zero'th law of ocsenave@0: thermodynamics.\rdquo{} Since nothing prevents us from regarding a ocsenave@0: thermometer as the \ldquo{}third body\rdquo{} in the above statement, ocsenave@0: it appears that we may also state the zero'th law as: ocsenave@0: #+begin_quote ocsenave@0: /Two bodies are in thermal equilibrium with each other when they are ocsenave@0: at the same temperature./ ocsenave@0: #+end_quote ocsenave@0: Although from the preceding discussion it might appear that ocsenave@0: these two statements of the zero'th law are entirely equivalent ocsenave@0: (and we certainly have no empirical evidence against either), it ocsenave@0: is interesting to note that there are theoretical reasons, arising ocsenave@0: from General Relativity, indicating that while the first ocsenave@0: statement may be universally valid, the second is not. When we ocsenave@0: consider equilibrium in a gravitational field, the verification ocsenave@0: that two bodies have equal temperatures may require transport ocsenave@0: of the thermometer through a gravitational potential difference; ocsenave@0: and this introduces a new element into the discussion. We will ocsenave@0: consider this in more detail in a later Chapter, and show that ocsenave@0: according to General Relativity, equilibrium in a large system ocsenave@0: requires, not that the temperature be uniform at all points, but ocsenave@0: rather that a particular function of temperature and gravitational ocsenave@0: potential be constant (the function is \(T\cdot \exp{(\Phi/c^2})\), where ocsenave@0: \(T\) is the Kelvin temperature to be defined later, and \(\Phi\) is the ocsenave@0: gravitational potential). ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Of course, this effect is so small that ordinary terrestrial ocsenave@0: experiments would need to have a precision many orders of ocsenave@0: magnitude beyond that presently possible, before one could hope even ocsenave@0: to detect it; and needless to say, it has played no role in the ocsenave@0: development of thermodynamics. For present purposes, therefore, ocsenave@0: we need not distinguish between the two above statements of the ocsenave@0: zero'th law, and we take it as a basic empirical fact that a ocsenave@0: uniform temperature at all points of a system is an essential ocsenave@0: condition for equilibrium. It is an important part of our ocsenave@0: ivestigation to determine whether there are other essential ocsenave@0: conditions as well. In fact, as we will find, there are many ocsenave@0: different kinds of equilibrium; and failure to distinguish between ocsenave@0: them can be a prolific source of paradoxes. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: ** Equation of State ocsenave@0: Another important reproducible connection is found when ocsenave@0: we consider a thermodynamic system defined by ocsenave@0: three parameters; in addition to the temperature we choose a ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{} and a conjugate \ldquo{}force.\rdquo{} ocsenave@0: Subject to some qualifications given below, we find experimentally ocsenave@0: that these parameters are not independent, but are subject to a constraint. ocsenave@0: For example, we cannot vary the equilibrium pressure, volume, ocsenave@0: and temperature of a given mass of gas independently; it is found ocsenave@0: that a given pressure and volume can be realized only at one ocsenave@0: particular temperature, that the gas will assume a given tempera~ ocsenave@0: ture and volume only at one particular pressure, etc. Similarly, ocsenave@0: a stretched wire can be made to have arbitrarily assigned tension ocsenave@0: and elongation only if its temperature is suitably chosen, a ocsenave@0: dielectric will assume a state of given temperature and ocsenave@0: polarization at only one value of the electric field, etc. ocsenave@0: These simplest nontrivial thermodynamic systems (three ocsenave@0: parameters with one constraint) are said to possess two ocsenave@0: /degrees of freedom/; for the range of possible equilibrium states is defined ocsenave@0: by specifying any two of the variables arbitrarily, whereupon the ocsenave@0: third, and all others we may introduce, are determined. ocsenave@0: Mathematically, this is expressed by the existence of a functional ocsenave@0: relationship of the form[fn::Edit: The set of solutions to an equation ocsenave@0: like /f(X,x,t)=/ const. is called a /level set/. Here, Jaynes is ocsenave@0: saying that the quantities /X/, /x/, and /t/ follow a \ldquo{}functional ocsenave@0: rule\rdquo{}, so the set of physically allowed combinations of /X/, ocsenave@0: /x/, and /t/ in equilibrium states can be ocsenave@0: expressed as the level set of a function. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: But not every function expresses a constraint relation; for some ocsenave@0: functions, you can specify two of the variables, and the third will ocsenave@0: still be undetermined. (For example, if f=X^2+x^2+t^2-3, ocsenave@0: the level set /f(X,x,t)=0/ is a sphere, and specifying /x=1/, /t=1/ ocsenave@0: leaves you with two potential possibilities for /X/ =\pm 1.) ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: A function like /f/ has to possess one more propery in order to ocsenave@0: express a constraint relationship: it must be monotonic in ocsenave@0: each of its variables /X/, /x/, and /t/. ocsenave@0: #the partial derivatives of /f/ exist for every allowed combination of ocsenave@0: #inputs /x/, /X/, and /t/. ocsenave@0: In other words, the level set has to pass a sort of ocsenave@0: \ldquo{}vertical line test\rdquo{} for each of its variables.] ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: #Edit Here, Jaynes ocsenave@0: #is saying that it is possible to express the collection of allowed combinations \(\langle X,x,t \rangle\) of force, quantity, and temperature as a ocsenave@0: #[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_set][level set]] of some function \(f\). However, not all level sets represent constraint relations; consider \(f(X,x,t)=X^2+x^2+t^2-1\)=0. ocsenave@0: #In order to specify ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: \begin{equation} ocsenave@0: f(X,x,t) = O ocsenave@0: \end{equation} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: where $X$ is a generalized force (pressure, tension, electric or ocsenave@0: magnetic field, etc.), $x$ is the corresponding generalized ocsenave@0: displacement (volume, elongation, electric or magnetic polarization, ocsenave@0: etc.), and $t$ is the empirical temperature. Equation (1) is ocsenave@0: called /the equation of state/. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: At the risk of belaboring it, we emphasize once again that ocsenave@0: all of this applies only for a system in equilibrium; for ocsenave@0: otherwise not only.the temperature, but also some or all of the other ocsenave@0: variables may not be definable. For example, no unique pressure ocsenave@0: can be assigned to a gas which has just suffered a sudden change ocsenave@0: in volume, until the generated sound waves have died out. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Independently of its functional form, the mere fact of the ocsenave@0: /existence/ of an equation of state has certain experimental ocsenave@0: consequences. For example, suppose that in experiments on oxygen ocsenave@0: gas, in which we control the temperature and pressure ocsenave@0: independently, we have found that the isothermal compressibility $K$ ocsenave@0: varies with temperature, and the thermal expansion coefficient ocsenave@0: \alpha varies with pressure $P$, so that within the accuracy of the data, ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: \begin{equation} ocsenave@0: \frac{\partial K}{\partial t} = - \frac{\partial \alpha}{\partial P} ocsenave@0: \end{equation} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Is this a particular property of oxygen; or is there reason to ocsenave@0: believe that it holds also for other substances? Does it depend ocsenave@0: on our particular choice of a temperature scale? ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: In this case, the answer is found at once; for the definitions of $K$, ocsenave@0: \alpha are ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: \begin{equation} ocsenave@0: K = -\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial P},\qquad ocsenave@0: \alpha=\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial t} ocsenave@0: \end{equation} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: which is simply a mathematical expression of the fact that the ocsenave@0: volume $V$ is a definite function of $P$ and $t$; i.e., it depends ocsenave@0: only ocsenave@0: on their present values, and not how those values were attained. ocsenave@0: In particular, $V$ does not depend on the direction in the \((P, t)\) ocsenave@0: plane through which the present values were approached; or, as we ocsenave@0: usually say it, \(dV\) is an /exact differential/. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Therefore, although at first glance the relation (2) appears ocsenave@0: nontrivial and far from obvious, a trivial mathematical analysis ocsenave@0: convinces us that it must hold regardless of our particular ocsenave@0: temperature scale, and that it is true not only of oxygen; it must ocsenave@0: hold for any substance, or mixture of substances, which possesses a ocsenave@0: definite, reproducible equation of state \(f(P,V,t)=0\). ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: But this understanding also enables us to predict situations in which ocsenave@0: (2) will /not/ hold. Equation (2), as we have just learned, expresses ocsenave@0: the fact that an equation of state exists involving only the three ocsenave@0: variables \((P,V,t)\). Now suppose we try to apply it to a liquid such ocsenave@0: as nitrobenzene. The nitrobenzene molecule has a large electric dipole ocsenave@0: moment; and so application of an electric field (as in the ocsenave@0: [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kerr_effect][electro-optical Kerr cell]]) causes an alignment of molecules which, as ocsenave@0: accurate measurements will verify, changes the pressure at a given ocsenave@0: temperature and volume. Therefore, there can no longer exist any ocsenave@0: unique equation of state involving \((P, V, t)\) only; with ocsenave@0: sufficiently accurate measurements, nitrobenzene must be regarded as a ocsenave@0: thermodynamic system with at least three degrees of freedom, and the ocsenave@0: general equation of state must have at least a complicated a form as ocsenave@0: \(f(P,V,t,E) = 0\). ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: But if we introduce a varying electric field $E$ into the discussion, ocsenave@0: the resulting varying electric polarization $M$ also becomes a new ocsenave@0: thermodynamic variable capable of being measured. Experimentally, it ocsenave@0: is easiest to control temperature, pressure, and electric field ocsenave@0: independently, and of course we find that both the volume and ocsenave@0: polarization are then determined; i.e., there must exist functional ocsenave@0: relations of the form \(V = V(P,t,E)\), \(M = M(P,t,E)\), or in more ocsenave@0: symmetrical form ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: \begin{equation} ocsenave@0: f(V,P,t,E) = 0 \qquad g(M,P,t,E)=0. ocsenave@0: \end{equation} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: In other words, if we regard nitrobenzene as a thermodynamic system of ocsenave@0: three degrees of freedom (i.e., having specified three parameters ocsenave@0: arbitrarily, all others are then determined), it must possess two ocsenave@0: independent equations of state. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Similarly, a thermodynamic system with four degrees of freedom, ocsenave@0: defined by the termperature and three pairs of conjugate forces and ocsenave@0: displacements, will have three independent equations of state, etc. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: Now, returning to our original question, if nitrobenzene possesses ocsenave@0: this extra electrical degree of freedom, under what circumstances do ocsenave@0: we exprect to find a reproducible equation of state involving ocsenave@0: \((p,V,t)\) only? Evidently, if $E$ is held constant, then the first ocsenave@0: of equations (1-5) becomes such an equation of state, involving $E$ as ocsenave@0: a fixed parameter; we would find many different equations of state of ocsenave@0: the form \(f(P,V,t) = 0\) with a different function $f$ for each ocsenave@0: different value of the electric field. Likewise, if \(M\) is held ocsenave@0: constant, we can eliminate \(E\) between equations (1-5) and find a ocsenave@0: relation \(h(P,V,t,M)=0\), which is an equation of state for ocsenave@0: \((P,V,t)\) containing \(M\) as a fixed parameter. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: More generally, if an electrical constraint is imposed on the system ocsenave@0: (for example, by connecting an external charged capacitor to the ocsenave@0: electrodes) so that \(M\) is determined by \(E\); i.e., there is a ocsenave@0: functional relation of the form ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: \begin{equation} ocsenave@0: g(M,E) = \text{const.} ocsenave@0: \end{equation} ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: then (1-5) and (1-6) constitute three simultaneous equations, from ocsenave@0: which both \(E\) and \(M\) may be eliminated mathematically, leading ocsenave@0: to a relation of the form \(h(P,V,t;q)=0\), which is an equation of ocsenave@0: state for \((P,V,t)\) involving the fixed parameter \(q\). ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: We see, then, that as long as a fixed constraint of the form (1-6) is ocsenave@0: imposed on the electrical degree of freedom, we can still observe a ocsenave@0: reproducible equation of state for nitrobenzene, considered as a ocsenave@0: thermodynamic system of only two degrees of freedom. If, however, this ocsenave@0: electrical constraint is removed, so that as we vary $P$ and $t$, the ocsenave@0: values of $E$ and $M$ vary in an uncontrolled way over a ocsenave@0: /two-dimensional/ region of the \((E, M)\) plane, then we will find no ocsenave@0: definite equation of state involving only \((P,V,t)\). ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: This may be stated more colloqually as follows: even though a system ocsenave@0: has three degrees of freedom, we can still consider only the variables ocsenave@0: belonging to two of them, and we will find a definite equation of ocsenave@0: state, /provided/ that in the course of the experiments, the unused ocsenave@0: degree of freedom is not \ldquo{}tampered with\rdquo{} in an ocsenave@0: uncontrolled way. ocsenave@0: ocsenave@0: We have already emphasized that any physical system corresponds to ocsenave@0: many different thermodynamic systems, depending on which variables we ocsenave@0: choose to control and measure. In fact, it is easy to see that any ocsenave@0: physical system has, for all practical purposes, an /arbitrarily ocsenave@0: large/ number of degrees of freedom. In the case of nitrobenzene, for ocsenave@0: example, we may impose any variety of nonuniform electric fields on ocsenave@0: our sample. Suppose we place $(n+1)$