Mercurial > jaynes
comparison org/stat-mech.org @ 0:26acdaf2e8c7
beginit begins.
author | Dylan Holmes <ocsenave@gmail.com> |
---|---|
date | Sat, 28 Apr 2012 19:32:50 -0500 |
parents | |
children | 4da2176e4890 |
comparison
equal
deleted
inserted
replaced
-1:000000000000 | 0:26acdaf2e8c7 |
---|---|
1 #+TITLE: Statistical Mechanics | |
2 #+AUTHOR: E.T. Jaynes; edited by Dylan Holmes | |
3 #+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu | |
4 #+KEYWORDS: statistical mechanics, thermostatics, thermodynamics, temperature, paradoxes, Jaynes | |
5 #+SETUPFILE: ../../aurellem/org/setup.org | |
6 #+INCLUDE: ../../aurellem/org/level-0.org | |
7 #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"http://www.aurellem.org/MathJax/MathJax.js" | |
8 | |
9 # "extensions/eqn-number.js" | |
10 | |
11 #+begin_quote | |
12 *Note:* The following is a typeset version of | |
13 [[../sources/stat.mech.1.pdf][this unpublished book draft]], written by [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Edwin_Thompson_Jaynes][E.T. Jaynes]]. I have only made | |
14 minor changes, e.g. to correct typographical errors, add references, or format equations. The | |
15 content itself is intact. --- Dylan | |
16 #+end_quote | |
17 | |
18 * Development of Thermodynamics | |
19 Our first intuitive, or \ldquo{}subjective\rdquo{} notions of temperature | |
20 arise from the sensations of warmth and cold associated with our | |
21 sense of touch . Yet science has been able to convert this qualitative | |
22 sensation into an accurately defined quantitative notion, | |
23 which can be applied far beyond the range of our direct experience. | |
24 Today an experimentalist will report confidently that his | |
25 spin system was at a temperature of 2.51 degrees Kelvin; and a | |
26 theoretician will report with almost as much confidence that the | |
27 temperature at the center of the sun is about \(2 \times 10^7\) degrees | |
28 Kelvin. | |
29 | |
30 The /fact/ that this has proved possible, and the main technical | |
31 ideas involved, are assumed already known to the reader; | |
32 and we are not concerned here with repeating standard material | |
33 already available in a dozen other textbooks . However | |
34 thermodynamics, in spite of its great successes, firmly established | |
35 for over a century, has also produced a great deal of confusion | |
36 and a long list of \ldquo{}paradoxes\rdquo{} centering mostly | |
37 around the second law and the nature of irreversibility. | |
38 For this reason and others noted below, we want to dwell here at | |
39 some length on the /logic/ underlying the development of | |
40 thermodynamics . Our aim is to emphasize certain points which, | |
41 in the writer's opinion, are essential for clearing up the | |
42 confusion and resolving the paradoxes; but which are not | |
43 sufficiently ernphasized---and indeed in many cases are | |
44 totally ignored---in other textbooks. | |
45 | |
46 This attention to logic | |
47 would not be particularly needed if we regarded classical | |
48 thermodynamics (or, as it is becoming called increasingly, | |
49 /thermostatics/) as a closed subject, in which the fundamentals | |
50 are already completely established, and there is | |
51 nothing more to be learned about them. A person who believes | |
52 this will probably prefer a pure axiomatic approach, in which | |
53 the basic laws are simply stated as arbitrary axioms, without | |
54 any attempt to present the evidence for them; and one proceeds | |
55 directly to working out their consequences. | |
56 However, we take the attitude here that thermostatics, for | |
57 all its venerable age, is very far from being a closed subject, | |
58 we still have a great deal to learn about such matters as the | |
59 most general definitions of equilibrium and reversibility, the | |
60 exact range of validity of various statements of the second and | |
61 third laws, the necessary and sufficient conditions for | |
62 applicability of thermodynamics to special cases such as | |
63 spin systems, and how thermodynamics can be applied to such | |
64 systems as putty or polyethylene, which deform under force, | |
65 but retain a \ldquo{}memory\rdquo{} of their past deformations. | |
66 Is it possible to apply thermodynamics to a system such as a vibrating quartz crystal? We can by | |
67 no means rule out the possibility that still more laws of | |
68 thermodynamics exist, as yet undiscovered, which would be | |
69 useful in such applications. | |
70 | |
71 | |
72 It is only by careful examination of the logic by which | |
73 present thermodynamics was created, asking exactly how much of | |
74 it is mathematical theorems, how much is deducible from the laws | |
75 of mechanics and electrodynamics, and how much rests only on | |
76 empirical evidence, how compelling is present evidence for the | |
77 accuracy and range of validity of its laws; in other words, | |
78 exactly where are the boundaries of present knowledge, that we | |
79 can hope to uncover new things. Clearly, much research is still | |
80 needed in this field, and we shall be able to accomplish only a | |
81 small part of this program in the present review. | |
82 | |
83 | |
84 It will develop that there is an astonishingly close analogy | |
85 with the logic underlying statistical theory in general, where | |
86 again a qualitative feeling that we all have (for the degrees of | |
87 plausibility of various unproved and undisproved assertions) must | |
88 be convertefi into a precisely defined quantitative concept | |
89 (probability). Our later development of probability theory in | |
90 Chapter 6,7 will be, to a considerable degree, a paraphrase | |
91 of our present review of the logic underlying classical | |
92 thermodynamics. | |
93 | |
94 ** The Primitive Thermometer. | |
95 | |
96 The earliest stages of our | |
97 story are necessarily speculative, since they took place long | |
98 before the beginnings of recorded history. But we can hardly | |
99 doubt that primitive man learned quickly that objects exposed | |
100 to the sun‘s rays or placed near a fire felt different from | |
101 those in the shade away from fires; and the same difference was | |
102 noted between animal bodies and inanimate objects. | |
103 | |
104 | |
105 As soon as it was noted that changes in this feeling of | |
106 warmth were correlated with other observable changes in the | |
107 behavior of objects, such as the boiling and freezing of water, | |
108 cooking of meat, melting of fat and wax, etc., the notion of | |
109 warmth took its first step away from the purely subjective | |
110 toward an objective, physical notion capable of being studied | |
111 scientifically. | |
112 | |
113 One of the most striking manifestations of warmth (but far | |
114 from the earliest discovered) is the almost universal expansion | |
115 of gases, liquids, and solids when heated . This property has | |
116 proved to be a convenient one with which to reduce the notion | |
117 of warmth to something entirely objective. The invention of the | |
118 /thermometer/, in which expansion of a mercury column, or a gas, | |
119 or the bending of a bimetallic strip, etc. is read off on a | |
120 suitable scale, thereby giving us a /number/ with which to work, | |
121 was a necessary prelude to even the crudest study of the physical | |
122 nature of heat. To the best of our knowledge, although the | |
123 necessary technology to do this had been available for at least | |
124 3,000 years, the first person to carry it out in practice was | |
125 Galileo, in 1592. | |
126 | |
127 Later on we will give more precise definitions of the term | |
128 \ldquo{}thermometer.\rdquo{} But at the present stage we | |
129 are not in a position to do so (as Galileo was not), because | |
130 the very concepts needed have not yet been developed; | |
131 more precise definitions can be | |
132 given only after our study has revealed the need for them. In | |
133 deed, our final definition can be given only after the full | |
134 mathematical formalism of statistical mechanics is at hand. | |
135 | |
136 Once a thermometer has been constructed, and the scale | |
137 marked off in a quite arbitrary way (although we will suppose | |
138 that the scale is at least monotonic: i.e., greater warmth always | |
139 corresponds to a greater number), we are ready to begin scien | |
140 tific experiments in thermodynamics. The number read eff from | |
141 any such instrument is called the /empirical temperature/, and we | |
142 denote it by \(t\). Since the exact calibration of the thermometer | |
143 is not specified), any monotonic increasing function | |
144 \(t‘ = f(t)\) provides an equally good temperature scale for the | |
145 present. | |
146 | |
147 | |
148 ** Thermodynamic Systems. | |
149 | |
150 The \ldquo{}thermodynamic systems\rdquo{} which | |
151 are the objects of our study may be, physically, almost any | |
152 collections of objects. The traditional simplest system with | |
153 which to begin a study of thermodynamics is a volume of gas. | |
154 We shall, however, be concerned from the start also with such | |
155 things as a stretched wire or membrane, an electric cell, a | |
156 polarized dielectric, a paramagnetic body in a magnetic field, etc. | |
157 | |
158 The /thermodynamic state/ of such a system is determined by | |
159 specifying (i.e., measuring) certain macrcoscopic physical | |
160 properties. Now, any real physical system has many millions of such | |
161 preperties; in order to have a usable theory we cannot require | |
162 that /all/ of them be specified. We see, therefore, that there | |
163 must be a clear distinction between the notions of | |
164 \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} and \ldquo{}physical | |
165 system.\rdquo{} | |
166 A given /physical/ system may correspond to many different | |
167 /thermodynamic systems/, depending | |
168 on which variables we choose to measure or control; and which | |
169 we decide to leave unmeasured and/or uncontrolled. | |
170 | |
171 | |
172 For example, our physical system might consist of a crystal | |
173 of sodium chloride. For one set of experiments we work with | |
174 temperature, volume, and pressure; and ignore its electrical | |
175 properties. For another set of experiments we work with | |
176 temperature, electric field, and electric polarization; and | |
177 ignore the varying stress and strain. The /physical/ system, | |
178 therefore, corresponds to two entirely different /thermodynamic/ | |
179 systems. Exactly how much freedom, then, do we have in choosing | |
180 the variables which shall define the thermodynamic state of our | |
181 system? How many must we choose? What [criteria] determine when | |
182 we have made an adequate choice? These questions cannot be | |
183 answered until we say a little more about what we are trying to | |
184 accomplish by a thermodynamic theory. A mere collection of | |
185 recorded data about our system, as in the [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/CRC_Handbook_of_Chemistry_and_Physics][/Handbook of Physics and | |
186 Chemistry/]], is a very useful thing, but it hardly constitutes | |
187 a theory. In order to construct anything deserving of such a | |
188 name, the primary requirement is that we can recognize some kind | |
189 of reproducible connection between the different properties con | |
190 sidered, so that information about some of them will enable us | |
191 to predict others. And of course, in order that our theory can | |
192 be called thermodynamics (and not some other area of physics), | |
193 it is necessary that the temperature be one of the quantities | |
194 involved in a nontrivial way. | |
195 | |
196 The gist of these remarks is that the notion of | |
197 \ldquo{}thermodynamic system\rdquo{} is in part | |
198 an anthropomorphic one; it is for us to | |
199 say which set of variables shall be used. If two different | |
200 choices both lead to useful reproducible connections, it is quite | |
201 meaningless to say that one choice is any more \ldquo{}correct\rdquo{} | |
202 than the other. Recognition of this fact will prove crucial later in | |
203 avoiding certain ancient paradoxes. | |
204 | |
205 At this stage we can determine only empirically which other | |
206 physical properties need to be introduced before reproducible | |
207 connections appear. Once any such connection is established, we | |
208 can analyze it with the hope of being able to (1) reduce it to a | |
209 /logical/ connection rather than an empirical one; and (2) extend | |
210 it to an hypothesis applying beyond the original data, which | |
211 enables us to predict further connections capable of being | |
212 tested by experiment. Examples of this will be given presently. | |
213 | |
214 | |
215 There will remain, however, a few reproducible relations | |
216 which to the best of present knowledge, are not reducible to | |
217 logical relations within the context of classical thermodynamics | |
218 (and. whose demonstration in the wider context of mechanics, | |
219 electrodynamics, and quantum theory remains one of probability | |
220 rather than logical proof); from the standpoint of thermodynamics | |
221 these remain simply statements of empirical fact which must be | |
222 accepted as such without any deeper basis, but without which the | |
223 development of thermodynamics cannot proceed. Because of this | |
224 special status, these relations have become known as the | |
225 \ldquo{}laws\rdquo{} | |
226 of thermodynamics . The most fundamental one is a qualitative | |
227 rather than quantitative relation, the \ldquo{}zero'th law.\rdquo{} | |
228 | |
229 ** Equilibrium; the \ldquo{}Zero‘th Law.\rdquo{} | |
230 | |
231 It is a common experience | |
232 that when objects are placed in contact with each other but | |
233 isolated from their surroundings, they may undergo observable | |
234 changes for a time as a result; one body may become warmer, | |
235 another cooler, the pressure of a gas or volume of a liquid may | |
236 change; stress or magnetization in a solid may change, etc. But | |
237 after a sufficient time, the observable macroscopic properties | |
238 settle down to a steady condition, after which no further changes | |
239 are seen unless there is a new intervention from the outside. | |
240 When this steady condition is reached, the experimentalist says | |
241 that the objects have reached a state of /equilibrium/ with each | |
242 other. Once again, more precise definitions of this term will | |
243 be needed eventually, but they require concepts not yet developed. | |
244 In any event, the criterion just stated is almost the only one | |
245 used in actual laboratory practice to decide when equilibrium | |
246 has been reached. | |
247 | |
248 | |
249 A particular case of equilibrium is encountered when we | |
250 place a thermometer in contact with another body. The reading | |
251 \(t\) of the thermometer may vary at first, but eventually it reach es | |
252 a steady value. Now the number \(t\) read by a thermometer is always. | |
253 by definition, the empirical temperature /of the thermometer/ (more | |
254 precisely, of the sensitive element of the thermometer). When | |
255 this number is constant in time, we say that the thermometer is | |
256 in /thermal equilibrium/ with its surroundings; and we then extend | |
257 the notion of temperature, calling the steady value \(t\) also the | |
258 /temperature of the surroundings/. | |
259 | |
260 We have repeated these elementary facts, well known to every | |
261 child, in order to emphasize this point: Thermodynamics can be | |
262 a theory /only/ of states of equilibrium, because the very | |
263 procedure by which the temperature of a system is defined by | |
264 operational means, already presupposes the attainment of | |
265 equilibrium. Strictly speaking, therefore, classical | |
266 thermodynamics does not even contain the concept of a | |
267 \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} | |
268 | |
269 Of course, to recognize this limitation on conventional | |
270 thermodynamics (best emphasized by calling it instead, | |
271 thermostatics) in no way rules out the possibility of | |
272 generalizing the notion of temperature to nonequilibrium states. | |
273 Indeed, it is clear that one could define any number of | |
274 time-dependent quantities all of which reduce, in the special | |
275 case of equilibrium, to the temperature as defined above. | |
276 Historically, attempts to do this even antedated the discovery | |
277 of the laws of thermodynamics, as is demonstrated by | |
278 \ldquo{}Newton's law of cooling.\rdquo{} Therefore, the | |
279 question is not whether generalization is /possible/, but only | |
280 whether it is in any way /useful/; i.e., does the temperature so | |
281 generalized have any connection with other physical properties | |
282 of our system, so that it could help us to predict other things? | |
283 However, to raise such questions takes us far beyond the | |
284 domain of thermostatics; and the general laws of nonequilibrium | |
285 behavior are so much more complicated that it would be virtually | |
286 hopeless to try to unravel them by empirical means alone. For | |
287 example, even if two different kinds of thermometer are calibrated | |
288 so that they agree with each other in equilibrium situations, | |
289 they will not agree in general about the momentary value a | |
290 \ldquo{}time-varying temperature.\rdquo{} To make any real | |
291 progress in this area, we have to supplement empirical observation by the guidance | |
292 of a rather hiqhly-developed theory. The notion of a | |
293 time-dependent temperature is far from simple conceptually, and we | |
294 will find that nothing very helpful can be said about this until | |
295 the full mathematical apparatus of nonequilibrium statistical | |
296 mechanics has been developed. | |
297 | |
298 Suppose now that two bodies have the same temperature; i.e., | |
299 a given thermometer reads the same steady value when in contact | |
300 with either. In order that the statement, \ldquo{}two bodies have the | |
301 same temperature\rdquo{} shall describe a physi cal property of the bodies, | |
302 and not merely an accidental circumstance due to our having used | |
303 a particular kind of thermometer, it is necessary that /all/ | |
304 thermometers agree in assigning equal temperatures to them if | |
305 /any/ thermometer does . Only experiment is competent to determine | |
306 whether this universality property is true. Unfortunately, the | |
307 writer must confess that he is unable to cite any definite | |
308 experiment in which this point was subjected to a careful test. | |
309 That equality of temperatures has this absolute meaning, has | |
310 evidently been taken for granted so much that (like absolute | |
311 sirnultaneity in pre-relativity physics) most of us are not even | |
312 consciously aware that we make such an assumption in | |
313 thermodynamics. However, for the present we can only take it as a familiar | |
314 empirical fact that this condition does hold, not because we can | |
315 cite positive evidence for it, but because of the absence of | |
316 negative evidence against it; i.e., we think that, if an | |
317 exception had ever been found, this would have created a sensation in | |
318 physics, and we should have heard of it. | |
319 | |
320 We now ask: when two bodies are at the same temperature, | |
321 are they then in thermal equilibrium with each other? Again, | |
322 only experiment is competent to answer this; the general | |
323 conclusion, again supported more by absence of negative evidence | |
324 than by specific positive evidence, is that the relation of | |
325 equilibrium has this property: | |
326 #+begin_quote | |
327 /Two bodies in thermal equilibrium | |
328 with a third body, are thermal equilibrium with each other./ | |
329 #+end_quote | |
330 | |
331 This empirical fact is usually called the \ldquo{}zero'th law of | |
332 thermodynamics.\rdquo{} Since nothing prevents us from regarding a | |
333 thermometer as the \ldquo{}third body\rdquo{} in the above statement, | |
334 it appears that we may also state the zero'th law as: | |
335 #+begin_quote | |
336 /Two bodies are in thermal equilibrium with each other when they are | |
337 at the same temperature./ | |
338 #+end_quote | |
339 Although from the preceding discussion it might appear that | |
340 these two statements of the zero'th law are entirely equivalent | |
341 (and we certainly have no empirical evidence against either), it | |
342 is interesting to note that there are theoretical reasons, arising | |
343 from General Relativity, indicating that while the first | |
344 statement may be universally valid, the second is not. When we | |
345 consider equilibrium in a gravitational field, the verification | |
346 that two bodies have equal temperatures may require transport | |
347 of the thermometer through a gravitational potential difference; | |
348 and this introduces a new element into the discussion. We will | |
349 consider this in more detail in a later Chapter, and show that | |
350 according to General Relativity, equilibrium in a large system | |
351 requires, not that the temperature be uniform at all points, but | |
352 rather that a particular function of temperature and gravitational | |
353 potential be constant (the function is \(T\cdot \exp{(\Phi/c^2})\), where | |
354 \(T\) is the Kelvin temperature to be defined later, and \(\Phi\) is the | |
355 gravitational potential). | |
356 | |
357 Of course, this effect is so small that ordinary terrestrial | |
358 experiments would need to have a precision many orders of | |
359 magnitude beyond that presently possible, before one could hope even | |
360 to detect it; and needless to say, it has played no role in the | |
361 development of thermodynamics. For present purposes, therefore, | |
362 we need not distinguish between the two above statements of the | |
363 zero'th law, and we take it as a basic empirical fact that a | |
364 uniform temperature at all points of a system is an essential | |
365 condition for equilibrium. It is an important part of our | |
366 ivestigation to determine whether there are other essential | |
367 conditions as well. In fact, as we will find, there are many | |
368 different kinds of equilibrium; and failure to distinguish between | |
369 them can be a prolific source of paradoxes. | |
370 | |
371 ** Equation of State | |
372 Another important reproducible connection is found when | |
373 we consider a thermodynamic system defined by | |
374 three parameters; in addition to the temperature we choose a | |
375 \ldquo{}displacement\rdquo{} and a conjugate \ldquo{}force.\rdquo{} | |
376 Subject to some qualifications given below, we find experimentally | |
377 that these parameters are not independent, but are subject to a constraint. | |
378 For example, we cannot vary the equilibrium pressure, volume, | |
379 and temperature of a given mass of gas independently; it is found | |
380 that a given pressure and volume can be realized only at one | |
381 particular temperature, that the gas will assume a given tempera~ | |
382 ture and volume only at one particular pressure, etc. Similarly, | |
383 a stretched wire can be made to have arbitrarily assigned tension | |
384 and elongation only if its temperature is suitably chosen, a | |
385 dielectric will assume a state of given temperature and | |
386 polarization at only one value of the electric field, etc. | |
387 These simplest nontrivial thermodynamic systems (three | |
388 parameters with one constraint) are said to possess two | |
389 /degrees of freedom/; for the range of possible equilibrium states is defined | |
390 by specifying any two of the variables arbitrarily, whereupon the | |
391 third, and all others we may introduce, are determined. | |
392 Mathematically, this is expressed by the existence of a functional | |
393 relationship of the form[fn::Edit: The set of solutions to an equation | |
394 like /f(X,x,t)=/ const. is called a /level set/. Here, Jaynes is | |
395 saying that the quantities /X/, /x/, and /t/ follow a \ldquo{}functional | |
396 rule\rdquo{}, so the set of physically allowed combinations of /X/, | |
397 /x/, and /t/ in equilibrium states can be | |
398 expressed as the level set of a function. | |
399 | |
400 But not every function expresses a constraint relation; for some | |
401 functions, you can specify two of the variables, and the third will | |
402 still be undetermined. (For example, if f=X^2+x^2+t^2-3, | |
403 the level set /f(X,x,t)=0/ is a sphere, and specifying /x=1/, /t=1/ | |
404 leaves you with two potential possibilities for /X/ =\pm 1.) | |
405 | |
406 A function like /f/ has to possess one more propery in order to | |
407 express a constraint relationship: it must be monotonic in | |
408 each of its variables /X/, /x/, and /t/. | |
409 #the partial derivatives of /f/ exist for every allowed combination of | |
410 #inputs /x/, /X/, and /t/. | |
411 In other words, the level set has to pass a sort of | |
412 \ldquo{}vertical line test\rdquo{} for each of its variables.] | |
413 | |
414 #Edit Here, Jaynes | |
415 #is saying that it is possible to express the collection of allowed combinations \(\langle X,x,t \rangle\) of force, quantity, and temperature as a | |
416 #[[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Level_set][level set]] of some function \(f\). However, not all level sets represent constraint relations; consider \(f(X,x,t)=X^2+x^2+t^2-1\)=0. | |
417 #In order to specify | |
418 | |
419 \begin{equation} | |
420 f(X,x,t) = O | |
421 \end{equation} | |
422 | |
423 where $X$ is a generalized force (pressure, tension, electric or | |
424 magnetic field, etc.), $x$ is the corresponding generalized | |
425 displacement (volume, elongation, electric or magnetic polarization, | |
426 etc.), and $t$ is the empirical temperature. Equation (1) is | |
427 called /the equation of state/. | |
428 | |
429 At the risk of belaboring it, we emphasize once again that | |
430 all of this applies only for a system in equilibrium; for | |
431 otherwise not only.the temperature, but also some or all of the other | |
432 variables may not be definable. For example, no unique pressure | |
433 can be assigned to a gas which has just suffered a sudden change | |
434 in volume, until the generated sound waves have died out. | |
435 | |
436 Independently of its functional form, the mere fact of the | |
437 /existence/ of an equation of state has certain experimental | |
438 consequences. For example, suppose that in experiments on oxygen | |
439 gas, in which we control the temperature and pressure | |
440 independently, we have found that the isothermal compressibility $K$ | |
441 varies with temperature, and the thermal expansion coefficient | |
442 \alpha varies with pressure $P$, so that within the accuracy of the data, | |
443 | |
444 \begin{equation} | |
445 \frac{\partial K}{\partial t} = - \frac{\partial \alpha}{\partial P} | |
446 \end{equation} | |
447 | |
448 Is this a particular property of oxygen; or is there reason to | |
449 believe that it holds also for other substances? Does it depend | |
450 on our particular choice of a temperature scale? | |
451 | |
452 In this case, the answer is found at once; for the definitions of $K$, | |
453 \alpha are | |
454 | |
455 \begin{equation} | |
456 K = -\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial P},\qquad | |
457 \alpha=\frac{1}{V}\frac{\partial V}{\partial t} | |
458 \end{equation} | |
459 | |
460 which is simply a mathematical expression of the fact that the | |
461 volume $V$ is a definite function of $P$ and $t$; i.e., it depends | |
462 only | |
463 on their present values, and not how those values were attained. | |
464 In particular, $V$ does not depend on the direction in the \((P, t)\) | |
465 plane through which the present values were approached; or, as we | |
466 usually say it, \(dV\) is an /exact differential/. | |
467 | |
468 Therefore, although at first glance the relation (2) appears | |
469 nontrivial and far from obvious, a trivial mathematical analysis | |
470 convinces us that it must hold regardless of our particular | |
471 temperature scale, and that it is true not only of oxygen; it must | |
472 hold for any substance, or mixture of substances, which possesses a | |
473 definite, reproducible equation of state \(f(P,V,t)=0\). | |
474 | |
475 But this understanding also enables us to predict situations in which | |
476 (2) will /not/ hold. Equation (2), as we have just learned, expresses | |
477 the fact that an equation of state exists involving only the three | |
478 variables \((P,V,t)\). Now suppose we try to apply it to a liquid such | |
479 as nitrobenzene. The nitrobenzene molecule has a large electric dipole | |
480 moment; and so application of an electric field (as in the | |
481 [[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kerr_effect][electro-optical Kerr cell]]) causes an alignment of molecules which, as | |
482 accurate measurements will verify, changes the pressure at a given | |
483 temperature and volume. Therefore, there can no longer exist any | |
484 unique equation of state involving \((P, V, t)\) only; with | |
485 sufficiently accurate measurements, nitrobenzene must be regarded as a | |
486 thermodynamic system with at least three degrees of freedom, and the | |
487 general equation of state must have at least a complicated a form as | |
488 \(f(P,V,t,E) = 0\). | |
489 | |
490 But if we introduce a varying electric field $E$ into the discussion, | |
491 the resulting varying electric polarization $M$ also becomes a new | |
492 thermodynamic variable capable of being measured. Experimentally, it | |
493 is easiest to control temperature, pressure, and electric field | |
494 independently, and of course we find that both the volume and | |
495 polarization are then determined; i.e., there must exist functional | |
496 relations of the form \(V = V(P,t,E)\), \(M = M(P,t,E)\), or in more | |
497 symmetrical form | |
498 | |
499 \begin{equation} | |
500 f(V,P,t,E) = 0 \qquad g(M,P,t,E)=0. | |
501 \end{equation} | |
502 | |
503 In other words, if we regard nitrobenzene as a thermodynamic system of | |
504 three degrees of freedom (i.e., having specified three parameters | |
505 arbitrarily, all others are then determined), it must possess two | |
506 independent equations of state. | |
507 | |
508 Similarly, a thermodynamic system with four degrees of freedom, | |
509 defined by the termperature and three pairs of conjugate forces and | |
510 displacements, will have three independent equations of state, etc. | |
511 | |
512 Now, returning to our original question, if nitrobenzene possesses | |
513 this extra electrical degree of freedom, under what circumstances do | |
514 we exprect to find a reproducible equation of state involving | |
515 \((p,V,t)\) only? Evidently, if $E$ is held constant, then the first | |
516 of equations (1-5) becomes such an equation of state, involving $E$ as | |
517 a fixed parameter; we would find many different equations of state of | |
518 the form \(f(P,V,t) = 0\) with a different function $f$ for each | |
519 different value of the electric field. Likewise, if \(M\) is held | |
520 constant, we can eliminate \(E\) between equations (1-5) and find a | |
521 relation \(h(P,V,t,M)=0\), which is an equation of state for | |
522 \((P,V,t)\) containing \(M\) as a fixed parameter. | |
523 | |
524 More generally, if an electrical constraint is imposed on the system | |
525 (for example, by connecting an external charged capacitor to the | |
526 electrodes) so that \(M\) is determined by \(E\); i.e., there is a | |
527 functional relation of the form | |
528 | |
529 \begin{equation} | |
530 g(M,E) = \text{const.} | |
531 \end{equation} | |
532 | |
533 then (1-5) and (1-6) constitute three simultaneous equations, from | |
534 which both \(E\) and \(M\) may be eliminated mathematically, leading | |
535 to a relation of the form \(h(P,V,t;q)=0\), which is an equation of | |
536 state for \((P,V,t)\) involving the fixed parameter \(q\). | |
537 | |
538 We see, then, that as long as a fixed constraint of the form (1-6) is | |
539 imposed on the electrical degree of freedom, we can still observe a | |
540 reproducible equation of state for nitrobenzene, considered as a | |
541 thermodynamic system of only two degrees of freedom. If, however, this | |
542 electrical constraint is removed, so that as we vary $P$ and $t$, the | |
543 values of $E$ and $M$ vary in an uncontrolled way over a | |
544 /two-dimensional/ region of the \((E, M)\) plane, then we will find no | |
545 definite equation of state involving only \((P,V,t)\). | |
546 | |
547 This may be stated more colloqually as follows: even though a system | |
548 has three degrees of freedom, we can still consider only the variables | |
549 belonging to two of them, and we will find a definite equation of | |
550 state, /provided/ that in the course of the experiments, the unused | |
551 degree of freedom is not \ldquo{}tampered with\rdquo{} in an | |
552 uncontrolled way. | |
553 | |
554 We have already emphasized that any physical system corresponds to | |
555 many different thermodynamic systems, depending on which variables we | |
556 choose to control and measure. In fact, it is easy to see that any | |
557 physical system has, for all practical purposes, an /arbitrarily | |
558 large/ number of degrees of freedom. In the case of nitrobenzene, for | |
559 example, we may impose any variety of nonuniform electric fields on | |
560 our sample. Suppose we place $(n+1)$ |