rlm@2: #+TITLE: Synthetic Differential Geometry rlm@2: #+author: Dylan Holmes rlm@2: #+EMAIL: rlm@mit.edu rlm@2: #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"../MathJax/MathJax.js" rlm@2: #+STYLE: rlm@2: #+OPTIONS: H:3 num:t toc:t \n:nil @:t ::t |:t ^:t -:t f:t *:t <:t rlm@2: #+SETUPFILE: ../templates/level-0.org rlm@2: #+INCLUDE: ../templates/level-0.org rlm@2: #+BABEL: :noweb yes :results silent rlm@2: rlm@2: (My notes on Anders Kock's /Synthetic Differential Geometry/) rlm@2: rlm@2: * Revisiting the real line rlm@2: rlm@2: *Lines*, the kind which Euclid talked about, each constitute a commutative rlm@2: ring: you choose any two points on the line to be 0 and 1, then add rlm@2: and multiply as if you were dealing with real numbers $\mathbb{R}$. rlm@2: rlm@2: Euclid moreover uses the axiom that for any two points, /either/ they are the rlm@2: same point /or/ there is a unique line between them. Algebraically, rlm@2: this amounts to saying that each line is not only a commutative ring rlm@2: but a *field*, as well. This marks our first departure from euclidean rlm@2: geometry, as our first axiom denies that each line is a field. rlm@2: rlm@2: rlm@2: ** The first anti-euclidean axiom rlm@2: A point in a ring is called *nilpotent* if its square is rlm@2: zero. Normally (that is, in $\mathbb{R}^n$), only $0$ is rlm@2: nilpotent. Here, as a consequence of the following axiom, there will rlm@2: exist other elements that are nilpotent. These elements will rlm@2: encapsulate our intuitive idea of \ldquo{}infinitesimally small\rdquo{} numbers. rlm@2: rlm@2: #+begin_quote rlm@2: *Axiom 1:* Let $R$ be the line, considered as a commutative ring, and rlm@2: let $D\subset R$ be the set of nilpotent elements on the line. Then for any rlm@2: morphism $g:D\rightarrow R$, there exists a unique $b\in R$ such that rlm@2: rlm@2: \(\forall d\in D, g(d) = g(0)+ b\cdot d\) rlm@2: rlm@2: Intuitively, this unique $b$ is the slope of the function $g$ near rlm@2: zero. Because every morphism $g$ has exactly one such $b$, we have the rlm@2: following results: rlm@2: rlm@2: 1. The set $D$ of nilpotent elements contains more than rlm@2: just 0. Indeed, suppose the contrary: if $D=\{0\}$, then for any $g$, /every/ $b\in R$ has the rlm@2: property described above;\mdash{}$b$ isn't uniquely defined. rlm@2: 2. Pick $b_1$ and $b_2$ in $R$. If every nilpotent $d$ satisfies $d\cdot rlm@2: b_1 = d\cdot b_2$, then $b_1$ and $b_2$ are equal. rlm@2: rlm@2: ** The first axiom $\ldots$ in terms of arrows rlm@2: rlm@2: Define $\xi:R\times R\rightarrow R^D$ by \(\xi:(a,b)\mapsto (d\mapsto rlm@2: a+b\cdot d)\). The first axiom is equivalent to the statement rlm@2: \ldquo{}\xi is invertible (i.e., a bijection)\rdquo{} rlm@2: rlm@2: We give $R\times R$ the structure of an $R$-algebra by defining rlm@2: multiplication: \( (a_1,b_1)\star(a_2,b_2) = (a_1\cdot a_2,\quad rlm@2: a_1\cdot b_2 + a_2\cdot b_1)\). This is called *dual-numbers rlm@2: multiplication*, and is similar to muliplication of complex numbers. rlm@2: rlm@2: rlm@2: ** Ex rlm@2: 1. If $a$ and $b$ are nilpotent, then $ab$ is nilpotent. rlm@2: 2. Even if $a$ and $b$ are nilpotent, the sum $a+b$ may not be. rlm@2: 3. Even if $a+b$ is nilpotent, either summand $a$, $b$ may not be. rlm@2: 4. rlm@2: rlm@2: #+end_quote