Mercurial > dylan
view categorical/plausible.org @ 6:b2f55bcf6853
fixed comments
author | Robert McIntyre <rlm@mit.edu> |
---|---|
date | Fri, 28 Oct 2011 04:56:15 -0700 |
parents | b4de894a1e2e |
children |
line wrap: on
line source
1 #+TITLE: Categorification of Plausible Reasoning2 #+AUTHOR: Dylan Holmes3 #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"../MathJax/MathJax.js"4 * COMMENT #+OPTIONS: LaTeX:dvipng6 * Deductive and inductive posets8 ** Definition9 If you have a collection \(P\) of logical propositions, you can order them by10 implication: \(a\) precedes \(b\) if and only if \(a\) implies11 \(b\). This makes \(P\) into a poset. Since the ordering arose from12 deductive implication, we'll call this a /deductive poset/.14 If you have a deductive poset \(P\), you can create a related poset \(P^*\)15 as follows: the underlying set is the same, and for any two16 propositions \(a\) and \(b\) in \(P\), \(a\) precedes17 \(ab\) in \(P^*\). We'll call this an /inductive poset/.19 ** A canonical map from deductive posets to inductive posets20 Each poset corresponds with a poset-category, that is a category with21 at most one arrow between any two objects. Considered as categories,22 inductive and deuctive posets are related as follows: there is a map23 \(\mathscr{F}\) which sends each arrow \(a\rightarrow b\) in \(P\) to24 the arrow \(a\rightarrow ab\) in \(P^*\). In fact, since \(a\) implies25 \(b\) if and only if \(a = ab\), \(\mathscr{F}\) sends each arrow in \(P\) to26 an identity arrow in \(P^*\) (specifically, it sends the arrow27 \(a\rightarrow b\) to the identity arrow \(a\rightarrow a\)).30 ** Assigning plausibilities to inductive posets32 Inductive posets encode the relative (/qualitative/) plausibilities of its33 propositions: there exists an arrow \(x\rightarrow y\) only if \(x\)34 is at least as plausible as \(y\).36 *** Consistent reasoning as a commutative diagram37 Inductive categories enable the following neat trick: we can interpret38 the objects of \(P^*\) as states of given information and interpret39 each arrow \(a\rightarrow ab\) in \(P^*\) as an inductive inference: the arrow40 \(a\rightarrow ab\) represents an inferential leap from the state of41 knowledge where only \(a\) is given to the state of knowledge where42 both \(a\) and \(b\) are given\mdash{} in this way, it represents43 the process of inferring \(b\) when given \(a\), and we label the44 arrow with \((b|a)\).46 This trick has several important features that suggest its usefulness,47 namely48 - Composition of arrows corresponds to compound inference.49 - In the special case of deductive inference, the inferential arrow is an50 identity; the source and destination states of knowledge are the same.51 - One aspect of the consistency requirement of Jaynes[fn:1] takes the form of a52 commutative square: \(x\rightarrow ax \rightarrow abx\) =53 \(x\rightarrow bx \rightarrow abx\) is the categorified version of54 \((AB|X)=(A|X)\cdot(B|AX)=(B|X)\cdot(A|BX)\).55 - We can make plausibility assignments by enriching the inductive56 category \(P^*\) over some monoidal category, e.g. the set of real numbers57 (considered as a category) with its usual multiplication. /When we do/,58 the identity arrows of \(P^*\) \mdash{}corresponding to59 deductive inferences\mdash{} are assigned a value of certainty automatically.61 [fn:1] /(IIIa) If a conclusion can be reasoned out in more than one62 way, then every possible way must lead to the same result./65 *** Reciprocal probabilities66 The natural numbers have a comparatively concrete origin: they are the67 result of decategorifying the category of finite sets[fn:2], or the68 coequalizer of the arrows from a one-object category to a two-object69 category with a single nonidentity arrow. Extensions of the set of70 natural numbers\mdash{} such as71 the set of integers or rational numbers or real numbers\mdash{} strike72 me as being somewhat more abstract.74 Jaynes points out that our existing choice of scale for probabilities75 (i.e., the scale from 0 for impossibility to 1 for76 certainty) has a degree of freedom: any monotonic function of77 probability encodes the same information that probability does.79 With this in mind, it seems useful to use not /probability/ but80 /reciprocal probability/ instead. This scale, which we might81 tentatively call freeness, is a scale ranging 1 (certainty) to82 positive infinity (impossibility).84 In this way, the ``probability''85 associated with choosing one out of \(n\) indistinguishable choices86 becomes identified with \(n\).88 The entropy90 [fn:2] As Baez says.94 ** self-questions96 What circumstances would make \(\mathscr{F}\) an injection?98 What if \(P=\{\top,\bot\}\)?102 ** COMMENT103 Inductive and deductive posets are related as follows: there is a monotone104 inclusion map \(\mathscr{i}:P^*\hookrightarrow P\) which\mdash{} since \(a\)105 implies \(b\) is equivalent to \(a=ab\)\mdash{} sends comparable106 propositions in \(P\) to the same proposition in \(P^*\). Conversely,107 only comparable propositions in \(P\) are sent to the same proposition108 in \(P^*\).112 ** Inductive posets and plausibility114 * Inverse Probability