Mercurial > dylan
comparison categorical/plausible.org @ 2:b4de894a1e2e
initial import
author | Robert McIntyre <rlm@mit.edu> |
---|---|
date | Fri, 28 Oct 2011 00:03:05 -0700 |
parents | |
children |
comparison
equal
deleted
inserted
replaced
1:8d8278e09888 | 2:b4de894a1e2e |
---|---|
1 #+TITLE: Categorification of Plausible Reasoning | |
2 #+AUTHOR: Dylan Holmes | |
3 #+MATHJAX: align:"left" mathml:t path:"../MathJax/MathJax.js" | |
4 * COMMENT #+OPTIONS: LaTeX:dvipng | |
5 | |
6 * Deductive and inductive posets | |
7 | |
8 ** Definition | |
9 If you have a collection \(P\) of logical propositions, you can order them by | |
10 implication: \(a\) precedes \(b\) if and only if \(a\) implies | |
11 \(b\). This makes \(P\) into a poset. Since the ordering arose from | |
12 deductive implication, we'll call this a /deductive poset/. | |
13 | |
14 If you have a deductive poset \(P\), you can create a related poset \(P^*\) | |
15 as follows: the underlying set is the same, and for any two | |
16 propositions \(a\) and \(b\) in \(P\), \(a\) precedes | |
17 \(ab\) in \(P^*\). We'll call this an /inductive poset/. | |
18 | |
19 ** A canonical map from deductive posets to inductive posets | |
20 Each poset corresponds with a poset-category, that is a category with | |
21 at most one arrow between any two objects. Considered as categories, | |
22 inductive and deuctive posets are related as follows: there is a map | |
23 \(\mathscr{F}\) which sends each arrow \(a\rightarrow b\) in \(P\) to | |
24 the arrow \(a\rightarrow ab\) in \(P^*\). In fact, since \(a\) implies | |
25 \(b\) if and only if \(a = ab\), \(\mathscr{F}\) sends each arrow in \(P\) to | |
26 an identity arrow in \(P^*\) (specifically, it sends the arrow | |
27 \(a\rightarrow b\) to the identity arrow \(a\rightarrow a\)). | |
28 | |
29 | |
30 ** Assigning plausibilities to inductive posets | |
31 | |
32 Inductive posets encode the relative (/qualitative/) plausibilities of its | |
33 propositions: there exists an arrow \(x\rightarrow y\) only if \(x\) | |
34 is at least as plausible as \(y\). | |
35 | |
36 *** Consistent reasoning as a commutative diagram | |
37 Inductive categories enable the following neat trick: we can interpret | |
38 the objects of \(P^*\) as states of given information and interpret | |
39 each arrow \(a\rightarrow ab\) in \(P^*\) as an inductive inference: the arrow | |
40 \(a\rightarrow ab\) represents an inferential leap from the state of | |
41 knowledge where only \(a\) is given to the state of knowledge where | |
42 both \(a\) and \(b\) are given\mdash{} in this way, it represents | |
43 the process of inferring \(b\) when given \(a\), and we label the | |
44 arrow with \((b|a)\). | |
45 | |
46 This trick has several important features that suggest its usefulness, | |
47 namely | |
48 - Composition of arrows corresponds to compound inference. | |
49 - In the special case of deductive inference, the inferential arrow is an | |
50 identity; the source and destination states of knowledge are the same. | |
51 - One aspect of the consistency requirement of Jaynes[fn:1] takes the form of a | |
52 commutative square: \(x\rightarrow ax \rightarrow abx\) = | |
53 \(x\rightarrow bx \rightarrow abx\) is the categorified version of | |
54 \((AB|X)=(A|X)\cdot(B|AX)=(B|X)\cdot(A|BX)\). | |
55 - We can make plausibility assignments by enriching the inductive | |
56 category \(P^*\) over some monoidal category, e.g. the set of real numbers | |
57 (considered as a category) with its usual multiplication. /When we do/, | |
58 the identity arrows of \(P^*\) \mdash{}corresponding to | |
59 deductive inferences\mdash{} are assigned a value of certainty automatically. | |
60 | |
61 [fn:1] /(IIIa) If a conclusion can be reasoned out in more than one | |
62 way, then every possible way must lead to the same result./ | |
63 | |
64 | |
65 *** Reciprocal probabilities | |
66 The natural numbers have a comparatively concrete origin: they are the | |
67 result of decategorifying the category of finite sets[fn:2], or the | |
68 coequalizer of the arrows from a one-object category to a two-object | |
69 category with a single nonidentity arrow. Extensions of the set of | |
70 natural numbers\mdash{} such as | |
71 the set of integers or rational numbers or real numbers\mdash{} strike | |
72 me as being somewhat more abstract. | |
73 | |
74 Jaynes points out that our existing choice of scale for probabilities | |
75 (i.e., the scale from 0 for impossibility to 1 for | |
76 certainty) has a degree of freedom: any monotonic function of | |
77 probability encodes the same information that probability does. | |
78 | |
79 With this in mind, it seems useful to use not /probability/ but | |
80 /reciprocal probability/ instead. This scale, which we might | |
81 tentatively call freeness, is a scale ranging 1 (certainty) to | |
82 positive infinity (impossibility). | |
83 | |
84 In this way, the ``probability'' | |
85 associated with choosing one out of \(n\) indistinguishable choices | |
86 becomes identified with \(n\). | |
87 | |
88 The entropy | |
89 | |
90 [fn:2] As Baez says. | |
91 | |
92 | |
93 | |
94 ** self-questions | |
95 | |
96 What circumstances would make \(\mathscr{F}\) an injection? | |
97 | |
98 What if \(P=\{\top,\bot\}\)? | |
99 | |
100 | |
101 | |
102 ** COMMENT | |
103 Inductive and deductive posets are related as follows: there is a monotone | |
104 inclusion map \(\mathscr{i}:P^*\hookrightarrow P\) which\mdash{} since \(a\) | |
105 implies \(b\) is equivalent to \(a=ab\)\mdash{} sends comparable | |
106 propositions in \(P\) to the same proposition in \(P^*\). Conversely, | |
107 only comparable propositions in \(P\) are sent to the same proposition | |
108 in \(P^*\). | |
109 | |
110 | |
111 | |
112 ** Inductive posets and plausibility | |
113 | |
114 * Inverse Probability |